HERBERT
SPIGELBERG
THE
PHENOMENOLOGICAL MOVEMENT
MARTIN
HEIDEGGER (1889- ) AS A PHENOMENOLOGIST
I. On Understanding
Heidegger
The name of Martin
Heidegger overshadows the present scene not only of German but
also of Continental and Spanish-American philosophy. This very
fact implies an enigma, at least to the Anglo-American world. What
can account for the still growing fascination with a thinker of
Heidegger's type ? Certainly not the volume of his published
production. Besides, his largest work, Sein und Zeit, is a torso,
and according to his own recent announcement it will for ever
remain so. Yet it confronts its reader with a language and a style
of thinking more demanding, if not actually forbidding, than most
other philosophy, present or past. And while some of the
circumstances surrounding Heidegger's way of life are highly
unconventional compared with those of the typical German
university philosopher, neither his personality nor his appearance
are sufficient to account for his impact on the academic and
non-academic world.
It would be
misleading, however, to think that Heidegger has never made an
impression on Anglo-American thinkers. A measure of this
impression may be found in the tribute which an analytic
philosopher like Gilbert Ryle once paid to Heidegger in a review
of his magnum opus, which in spite of its severe strictures and
negative conclusions contained such sentences as the following:
I have nothing but
admiration for his special undertaking and for such of his
achievements in it as I can follow. . . . He shows himself to be a
thinker of real importance by the immense subtlety and
searchingness of his examination of consciousness, by the boldness
and originality of his methods and conclusions, and by the
unflagging energy with which he
272 THE GERMAN
PHASE
tries to think
beyond the stock categories of orthodox philosophy and
psychology.1
It is also worth
mentioning that after Sidney Hook's return from a study trip in
Germany in the early thirties John Dewey expressed to him
considerable interest in Heidegger, particularly in his conception
of the human situation and in his concept of concern (Sorge), to
which there are indeed not a few parallels in Dewey's own
thought.2
Another approach to
Heidegger's thinking is suggested by the present vogue of Paul
Tillich's Systematic Theology. For Tillich himself has
acknowledged the decisive influence which Heidegger's thought has
had on his work since 1924-25, when the two were colleagues at the
University of Marburg, i.e., during the time when Heidegger's Sein
und Zeit was in the making. 3 Heidegger's impact was even stronger
in the case of Rudolf Bultmann, whose so-called
"demythologization" (Entmythologisierung) of New
Testament theology is arousing increased interest even outside
Germany.4
But the fundamental
paradox remains. To resolve it fully one would have to consider
not only the voice which has aroused such an amazing echo but also
the acoustic conditions for its reception in Germany and in other
parts of the world. Even before that, a clear and complete
presentation and interpre-
1 Mind XXXVIII
(1929), 355-370.
2 Personal
communication; see also his Portrait: "John Dewey," The
American. Scholar XVII (1948), 108.
3 "In Marburg,
in 1925, I began work on my Systematic Theology, the first volume
of which appeared in 1951. At the same time that Heidegger was in
Marburg as professor of philosophy, influencing some of the best
students, existentialism in its twentieth century form crossed my
path. It was years before I became fully aware of the impact of
this encounter on my own thinking. I resisted, I tried to learn, I
accepted the new way of thinking more than the answers it
gave" (Kegley, Charles W. and Bretall, Robert W., eds., The
Theology of Paul Tillich. New York, Macmillan, 1952,
"Autobiographical Reflections," p. 14). - See also Paul
Tillich, The Interpretation of History (New York, Scribner, 1936),
p. 39 f. - Tillich's theology stresses, for instance, the
distinction between Being and "a being" very much as
Heidegger did from Sein und Zeit on; see Paul Tillich, Systematic
Theology I
(1951), p. 163 ff.;
Love, Power, and Justice (1954), pp. 18 ff. Also, Tillich's whole
conception of ontology, whose subject is described as being, as
distinguished from the sciences which deal with beings, reflects
Heidegger thought. To be sure, thus far Heidegger has steadfastly
refused to identify Being with God, as Tillich now does.
4 Here Heidegger's
existential interpretation is used as a means to determine just
what the non-mythical sense of the Biblical text implies. See
Dinkier, Erich, "Existentialist Interpretation of the New
Testament," Journal of Religion, XXXII
(1952), 87-96;
Macquarrie, John, An Existentialist Theology. A Comparison of
Heidegger and Bultmann (London, SCM Press, 1955).
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
273
tation of
Heidegger's entire philosophizing, as far as publicly accessible,
would be indispensable. Such an assignment would be a staggering
one. It must be left to those who are prepared to submerge
themselves in Heidegger's writings to the extent of pondering them
line by line like any classical text that requires interpretation
by a commentary, yet without giving up their critical attitude
toward his weird if impressive style.
Luckily, the needs
of the present enterprise are more limited. For all it requires is
to determine the connection between the Heideggerian enigma and
the Phenomenological Movement, on whose development Heidegger has
exerted such a fateful and almost fatal influence. This calls
merely for the discussion of the phenomenological aspect of his
work. To be sure, it cannot be taken for granted that such a
separation is feasible. But this possibility is at least suggested
by the fact that Heidegger himself has dropped all references to
phenomenology from his later writings.
The most formidable
hurdle for any attempt to understand Heidegger, particularly the
Heidegger of the decisive middle period, is no doubt linguistic.
No reader without an exceptional command of German can expect to
fathom the sense and the full connotations of Heidegger's
language. The delay in English translations is clearly related to
this primary difficulty. But even the native German finds himself
all too often stymied by Heidegger's way of writing, which would
almost call for a translation into ordinary German. For Heidegger
has a way of not only forming new terms based on obsolete root
meanings, but of using existing words for new and unheard-of
purposes without providing a glossary as a key or introducing his
new uses by explicit definitions. Thus even the German reader has
really no alternative to learning Heidegger's vocabulary just as
he learned his mother tongue, i.e., by watching its uses and by
trial and error. We shall see later that the problem of language
is actually the one which has blocked Heidegger's main attack on
his central problem.
The difficulties of
Heidegger's style would seem to deepen the enigma of his impact.
It therefore seems worth pointing out that it was not until the
appearance of Sein und, Zeit that Heidegger's literary style had
fully developed. Hardly any of his
274 THE GERMAN
PHASE
peculiarities occur
in his earlier publications, such as his thesis on Duns Scotus. In
fact, his initial success and reputation was built mainly on his
lecturing in Freiburg and Marburg and on the expectations it had
aroused. It was only on this foundation that the publication of
Sein und Zeit in volume VIII of Husserl's phenomenological
yearbook made such a deep impression. That the style of
Heidegger's teaching differed considerably from that of his
writing can be gathered from the recent publication of some of his
lecture courses. They show little of the knottiness of the central
sections of Sein und Zeit. In fact his lecturing is characterized
by its "clear and deliberate way," to which even a
master of clarity in the Anglo-American world like Ralph Barton
Perry testified after attending one of his classes. Also in
personal contacts, in his calm plainness and unassuming
directness, Heidegger presents a striking contrast not only to his
pontifical manner of writing and carefully timed desk performance,
but also to the aloofness typical of too many German scholars, a
contrast which may have contributed to making his amazing and
often mystifying message all the more effective.
However,
Heidegger's philosophical significance will have to rest on his
publications. There is no way of getting around these. Few, if
any, second-hand accounts can pave the way to them. Almost all of
those now available in English are marred by the mere fact that
they are found in the misleading context of accounts of
existentialism, which Heidegger repudiates. Most of them fail to
realize the development in Heidegger's thinking. And they are even
less adequate as introductions to the phenomenological aspects of
Heidegger's work. Thus the challenging problem of providing a real
introduction to Heidegger's thinking remains unsolved to this
hour. In stating this I do not mean to imply that it can be
solved, especially at this stage when important evidence is still
missing. Yet the attempt ought to be made, if only for the sake of
better relations between the main philosophical currents of our
time.
There is one final
suggestion which I would like to offer before turning to my
limited assignment, all the more since it has a bearing even on
the development of Heidegger's attitude toward the
phenomenological approach. Since Heidegger's Holderlin studies
began to appear in 1936, it has become manifest that
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
275
poetry holds a
unique place in Heidegger's thinking. In 1954 a little volume
"From the Experience of Thought" appeared in which two
short poems of his own surround a sequence of reflections
consisting of mood-setting half-sentences, striking in their
imagery, on one page, and quasi-Presocratic aphorisms on the
opposite page. They suggest a synthesis of the styles of Holderlin
and Parmenides, Heidegger's main guides in recent years. This turn
to poetry provides perhaps the best clue to Heidegger's secret. It
suggests at the same time that he is fundamentally much closer to
the poets of the world than to its pure philosophers. Coleridge,
Thoreau, and T. S. Eliot are more congenial to him than even a
philosopher-poet like Santayana.
2. Heidegger's
Place in the History of Phenomenology
How far is
Heidegger's thinking rightfully to be included in the history of
the Phenomenological Movement ? This question, which is of
considerable importance for the present enterprise, is usually not
even raised; nor is it easy to answer it.1 The accepted story,
especially among outsiders, says that Heidegger is Husserl's
legitimate heir, as evidenced by his succession to Husserl's chair
in Freiburg; that consequently Heidegger's philosophy represents
the rightful development of Husserl's phenomenology; and that the
case for or against phenomenology can be settled by looking at its
logical outcome in Heidegger's work. But there are also those who,
partly because of their better knowledge of Husserl's final
repudiation of Heidegger's thinking, and perhaps also from a
desire to acquit phenomenology of responsibility for Heidegger's
philosophy of existence, see in him merely a corruptor of, or even
a deserter from, "orthodox" phenomenology.
The history of
Heidegger's association with phenomenology is almost entirely the
history of his association with Edmund Husserl. His contacts with
Scheler in the later twenties came at a time when Scheler's
interest in phenomenology as such had weakened considerably, and
when philosophical anthropology
1 See however
Delfgaauw, B., "La phenomenologie chez Martin
Heidegger," 6tudes philosophiques IX (1954), 50-56, and
Hyppolite, Jean, "Ontologie et phenomenologie chez Martin
Heidegger," ibid. 307-14.
276 THE GERMAN
PHASE
was their main
common concern. No serious contacts with the Munich Circle seem to
have occurred.
A final appraisal
of the relationship between Husserl and Heidegger presupposes
first of all adequate knowledge of the facts. To be sure,
important evidence, such as the complete Husserl-Heidegger
correspondence, is still inacccessible. But enough material is
available to reconstruct at least the outline of the story. As far
as Husserl's side of the relationship is concerned, it has all the
earmarks of a personal tragedy, where fault-finding would be as
futile as it would be silly. Besides, most of it is irrelevant to
our story, which concerns only the temporary association and final
estrangement between two thinkers too independent-minded and too
committed to their distinctive tasks to allow more than a
temporary association. There is, however, need for a simple
recording of the chronological facts in this relationship.
Apparently there
were no personal contacts between Husserl and Heidegger during the
Gottingen period. True, Heidegger's interest in Husserl was strong
enough to make him wish for a chance to study under him
personally. But financial necessities prevented this and forced
him to complete his studies at the University of Freiburg in his
native state of Baden.1 When Husserl arrived in Freiburg in 1916,
Heidegger had not only completed his academic education under
Heinrich Rickert, but had been admitted to the faculty as a
Privatdozent, whose inaugural lecture on July 27, 1915 dealt with
the concept of time in historiography. The preface to his
habilitation thesis on Duns Scotus, in which he acknowledged
Husserl's help in connection with his request for a publication
grant, suggests that the first personal meetings occurred
immediately upon Husserl's arrival. But it was apparently not
until the end of Heidegger's military service during the First
World War and the beginning of his full scale teaching that closer
contact was established. Heidegger was therefore never Husserl's
pupil in a sense of the term which would justify the expectation
of a special personal loyalty to Husserl, any more than this could
be expected of the Munich phenomenologists. Moreover, Heidegger
was an established scholar in his own right, with a record of
several publications,
1 Oral
communication.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
277
before he had ever
met Husserl. However from then on an intense philosophical and
personal relationship and friendship between the full professor
and the young Privatdozent began to take shape, particularly after
Heidegger had become Husserl's assistant in his academic duties.
In order to fully understand this relationship one has to realize
that Husserl started his Freiburg teaching with an almost entirely
new group of students, Edith Stein being the only candidate for
the Ph.D. degree, soon to become his private assistant, who had
come with him. What was even more important, Husserl's
philosophical development since the publication of the first
volume of his Ideen with its new idealistic interpretation of
phenomenology had left him practically isolated. All the more
anxious was he to attract mature students and scholars as
collaborators in the tasks of coping with an ever increasing
number of new problems and of organizing the accumulating piles of
his manuscripts. Husserl soon discovered the originality and vigor
of his new colleague. At the same time, Heidegger's lively
interest in phenomenology aroused in him hopes for close
co-operation, especially after his forthcoming retirement, and of
Heidegger's eventual succession to and continuation of his own
work where he would have to leave off. It is probably an
unanswerable question how far Heidegger himself gave encouragement
to this hope. However, the fact that Heidegger identified himself
with the cause of phenomenology is manifest from the very titles
of his lectures from 1919 on, when he first announced a course on
"Phenomenology and Transcendental Philosophy of Value,"
the latter meaning clearly the Neo-Kantian value theory of
Heinrich Rickert. From then on until his transfer to Marburg as
full professor in 1923, Heidegger offered every semester courses
and seminars in whose titles the word 'phenomenology' occurred.
This continued even during the five momentous years which he spent
in philosophical independence at Marburg. During the first
semester after his return to Freiburg as Husserl's successor, he
again announced pheno-menological seminars. All the more
conspicuous is the total absence of the word from Heidegger's
academic offerings after that, except in connection with a course
(in 1930-31) on Hegel's Phdnomenologie des Geistes.
There is parallel
evidence in Heidegger's publications. The
278 THE GERMAN
PHASE
Duns Scotus book of
1916, without expressing an explicit commitment, displayed intense
interest in Husserl's phenomenology and an attempt to use it for a
historical interpretation. Sein und Zeit, which appeared in the
phenomenological Jahrbuch while Heidegger was still in Marburg,
and which in its separate book edition carried a special
dedication to Husserl ("in Vereh-rung und
Freundschaft"), contained the most pronounced espousal of
phenomenology, although the specific references to Husserl are
relatively rare and insignificant. However, the word
"phenomenology" is missing in "Vom Wesen des
Grundes," Heidegger's contribution to the Festschrift for
Husserl's seventieth birthday in 1929, published one year after
Heidegger's return to Freiburg.1 Kant und das Problem der
Metaphysik, appearing during the same year, uses the term only
twice in relatively minor places in connection with the
characterization of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, which, in
Heidegger's eyes, turns out to be ultimately inadequate for a task
which he himself intends to complete by his new
Fundamentalontologie. After that I can trace only two more
explicit references to phenomenology in Heidegger's writings. Both
occur in the "Letter on Humanism" (1949), which includes
Heidegger's most illuminating philosophical autobiography thus
far. Here, after acknowledging the relative superiority of the
Marxian interpretation of history to all others (because of its
awareness of the alienation and homeless-ness of modern man in the
world) Heidegger states:
Since neither
Husserl nor Sartre, as far as I can see thus far, recognize the
essential place of the historical factor (das Geschichtliche) in
Being, neither phenomenology (die Phenomenology) nor
existentialism has entered the dimension in which alone a
constructive debate with Marxism can take place.2
This statement
sounds as if Heidegger had dissociated himself completely from all
phenomenology, and not only from Husserl's version of it. It
would, however, be rash to infer on the strength of one such
passage alone that Heidegger has repudiated phenomenology lock,
stock, and barrel. In the very same letter
1 This Festschrift,
whose editors are not mentioned, but which was clearly prepared by
Heidegger without the cooperation of the older collaborators of
the Jahrbuch, has no dedicatory preface, but carries a motto from
Plato's Sophistes (254 A), Heidegger's favorite Plato dialogue at
the time, which, in its characterization of the philosopher,
sounds like a curious homage to Husserl.
2 Platons Lehre van
der Wahrheit, p. 87.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
279
there occurs
another sentence which emphasizes that he wants to "hold on
to the essential help of phenomenological viewing" (die
wesentliche Hilfe des phanomenologischen Sehens}, while rejecting
the "improper aspiration" to "science"
(Wissenschaft) and "research" (Forschung) (p. 110).
Besides, Heidegger has never rejected the Phenomenological
Movement in its entirety. What, then, is the meaning of and the
deeper reason for his abandonment of all phenomenological
terminology? Here again it becomes important to secure more
factual information about the development of the relations between
Husserl and Heidegger in the period of their actual co-operation.
During Heidegger's
Marburg years his direct contacts with Husserl were naturally less
frequent, although Heidegger kept passing through Freiburg on the
way to his ski-hut in the Black Forest. There was, however, one
attempt at concrete co-operation whose failure throws considerable
light on the entire relationship. Presumably as a sequel to his
London lectures in 1922 Husserl was asked to write an article on
Phenomenology for the 13th edition of the Encyclopaedia
Britannica. He seems to have considered this occasion important
enough to invite Heidegger to collaborate with him on a joint
statement, based of course on his own draft: this would also give
him a chance to make Heidegger a more active participant in the
latest phase of his transcendental phenomenology. The history of
this article has been described in considerable detail, though not
exhaustively, by Walter Biemel.1 In the present context the
following documents deserve special attention:
oc. Heidegger's
unpublished independent draft of 1927, consisting of eleven
typewritten pages, clearly prepared after he had already completed
Sein und Zeit, with Husserl's annotations to it.
P. Heidegger's
comments on Husserl's main draft, representing Heidegger's attempt
to formulate the common ground as he saw it at the time.
Heidegger's draft
is particularly instructive if compared with Husserl's preceding
version. For here Husserl, after a brief introductory definition,
had started immediately with a dis-
1 "Husserl
Encyclopaedia Britannica Artikel und Heideggers Anmerkungen
dazu," Tijdschrift vow Philosophic XII (1950), 246-280.
280 THE GERMAN
PHASE
cussion of
phenomenological psychology. Thus making the subjective sphere his
point of departure, he had moved in the second part to the more
radical form of subjective phenomenology - transcendental
phenomenology. Heidegger's draft begins with a general
introduction of more than two typewritten pages dealing with
"the idea of philosophy and the regress (Ruckgang) to
consciousness," in which the primary concern of all
philosophy is characterized as "being qua being," which
is, as we shall see, Heidegger's one pervading theme. Parmenides
is mentioned as the first thinker to state it. Now to Heidegger
the remarkable thing is the fact that from the very start this
problem has been linked up with a reflection (Besinnung) upon the
thought about this "being." Phenomenology is then
characterized as "the basic realization of the necessity of a
regress to consciousness, the radical and express determination of
the way and of the laws governing the steps of this regress, and
the fundamental demarcation and the systematic explorations of the
field opened up during this regress." 1 While this
formulation seems to go far toward meeting Husserl's insistence on
the all-importance of the study of transcendental subjectivity,
Heidegger adds at once: "It stands in the service of ... the
question about the being of what is (Sein des Seienden} in the
articulated variety of its types and stages" - an addition
which establishes the connection with the theme of Sein und Zeit.
Psychology as a positive science is then declared incapable of
taking over the task of the needed science of subjective
experience in which transcendent being constitutes itself. - After
this introduction Heidegger's draft runs almost completely
parallel to Husserl's account of phenomenological psychology as
published in the rather free translation of the original in the
Encyclopaedia Britannica. The published version shows that Husserl
left out Heidegger's introduction completely. Judging from his
notes and bracketings, he seems to have objected particularly to
the passages in which Heidegger characterized the goal of
philosophy as concern with Being.
1 "Die
grundsatzliche Einsicht in die Notwendigkeit des Ruckganges auf
das Bewusstsein, die radikale und ausdruckliche Bestimmung des
Weges und der Schritt-gesetze dieses Ruckganges, die prinzipielle
Umgrenzung und systematische Durch-forschung des auf diesem
Ruckgang zu erschliessenden Feldes bezeichnen wir als
Phanomenologie.''
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
281
For the second part
of Husserl's article, entitled "Transcendental
Phenomenology," the Husserl Archives contain no draft from
Heidegger's hand. The half-empty last page of the typescript makes
it unlikely that there ever was one. There exists, however, a
letter from Heidegger, dated October 22, 1927, in which he
attempts to define his position with regard to transcendental
phenomenology and to the transcendental reduction in particular,
very much along the lines of the sections in Sein und Zeit which
discuss transcendental philosophy (pp. 207 ff.). Reading these
statements, particularly in retrospect and in the light of the
parallel statements and silences of Sein und Zeit, it seems
difficult not to see how completely Heidegger had moved away from
Husserl's position, how wide the gap between their interpretations
of phenomenology had become, and how little of Husserl's
transcendental philosophy, and particularly of his transcendental
reduction, was acceptable to Heidegger. In fact Husserl's letter
of December 26, 1927 to Roman Ingarden contained the statement
that "Heidegger has not grasped the whole meaning of the
phenomenological reduction." It is thus not surprising that
the final version of the Britannica article does not seem to
include any of Heidegger's draft. Thus the attempt to use the
occasion to bring about an agreement between the two protagonists
of Freiburg phenomenology had had just the opposite result.
A second case of an
attempted collaboration was Heidegger's editing of Husserl's
Gottingen lectures on inner time consciousness, dating back to
1905 and 1910, in the volume of the Jahr-buch (IX, 1929) that
followed immediately upon the publication of Sein und Zeit.
Heidegger's interest in such a topic was only natural. However,
his brief preface introduces these lectures merely as supplements
to the Logische Untersuchungen without so much as a reference to
Husserl's later intensified analyses. It may well be that it was
this fact which left Husserl disappointed with the results of
Heidegger's editing.
In spite of
mounting misgivings, Husserl clung to the hope that he could win
Heidegger over after his return to Freiburg. Hence he submitted
his name as that of his only qualified successor. None of this
hope materialized when Heidegger took over Husserl's chair in the
fall of 1928. Instead, after the first two months, their contacts
became less and less frequent.
282 THE GERMAN
PHASE
Around this time
Husserl also returned to an intensive study of Sein und Zeit,
partly with the aid of his new assistant, Eugen Fink, who had been
trained by both Husserl and Heidegger. His marginal comments to
this work and to Heidegger's Kant book (Kant und das Problem der
Metaphysik) reveal his growing awareness of the differences
between himself and Heidegger and his suspicion of hidden attacks
in Heidegger's text.1 Apparently his main impression was that
Heidegger, by substituting human existence (Dasein) for the pure
ego, had transformed phenomenology into anthropology, the very
same anthropology which Husserl had once fought in the first
volume of his Logische Untersuchungen as a species of
psychologism. The absence of any reference to Husserl's doctrine
of the phe-nomenological or transcendental reduction and, in fact,
to practically all of his recent work made him conclude that
Heidegger's phenomenology had not yet passed beyond the natural or
"naive" attitude, and that his philosophy was simply
another form of "objectivism," "naturalism,"
or "realism."
Indications are
that Husserl began to express his disapproval of Heidegger's
phenomenology with increasing frankness soon after Heidegger's
return to Freiburg. The most explicit repudiation of Heidegger's
philosophizing appeared on the last pages of the terminal volume
of the Jahrbuch (XI, 1930), notably in a Nachwort to the Ideen,
which presented a slightly amplified version of Husserl's preface
to the English translation by W. R. Boyce Gibson. Here, in an
opening section omitted from the translation, Husserl protested
against certain objections not explicitly listed, but clearly
attributed to Heidegger, and declared sweepingly that all of them
were
based on
misunderstandings and fundamentally upon the fact that one
misinterprets my phenomenology backwards from a level which it was
its very purpose to overcome, in other words, that one has failed
to understand the fundamental novelty of the phenomenological
reduction and hence the progress from mundane subjectivity (i.e.,
man) to transcendental subjectivity; consequently that one has
remained stuck in an anthropology, whether empirical or a priori,
which according to my doctrine has not yet reached the genuine
philosophical level, and whose interpretation as philosophy means
a lapse into "transcendental anthro-pologism" or
"psychologism." 2
1 For samples of
these notes see Alwin Diemer, Edmund Husserl, p. 29 f.
2 JPPF XI (1930),
551; also Husserliana, V, 140.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
283
This charge was
pressed home further in a lecture on Phanomenologie und
Anthropologie" which Husserl gave in Berlin and Frankfurt in
1931,1 though still without mentioning Heidegger's name. Here
anthropologism, which Husserl characterizes as a psychologism that
builds phenomenology on human existence (menschliches Dasein], is
termed the diametrical opposite of transcendental phenomenology.
Around this time Husserl also began to refer to Heidegger and
Scheler as his philosophical antipodes.
These and similar
developments were responsible for the fact that Heidegger dropped
all references to phenomenology in his writings and lectures,
perhaps also in deference to Husserl's prior claim to the term.
Without a formal break, even personal contacts seem to have
subsided long before Heidegger became involved in national
socialism. There is no sign that Heidegger tried to alleviate
Husserl's difficulties during the Nazi regime. But it should be
pointed out that the humiliations meted out to Husserl as a
racially Jewish member of the Freiburg faculty occurred after the
end of Heidegger's official leadership of the university.
These ascertainable
facts make it plain that after Husserl's denunciation Heidegger no
longer considered himself a member of the Phenomenological
Movement in Husserl's sense. The quiet demise of the
phenomenological yearbook, whose management during these years had
been chiefly in the hands of Heidegger and Oskar Becker, himself a
much closer associate of Heidegger than of Husserl, is additional
evidence.
But this does not
settle the question whether Heidegger, in accepting Husserl's
"excommunication," also meant to dissociate himself from
the whole Phenomenological Movement in the wider sense. The fact
that he has failed to revive the fahrbuch would seem to suggest
that he is at least no longer interested in its continuation.
However, a final answer to this question will have to wait for the
discussion of Heidegger's own conception of phenomenology and its
development later on.
j. Heidegger's
Basic Theme: The Quest for Being and Time Before we pursue further
the question of the nature and function of Heidegger's
phenomenology it will be necessary to
1 PPR II (1941),
1-14.
284 THE GERMAN
PHASE
clarify Heidegger's
general philosophy and its development, at least to an extent
which will make it possible to determine and understand the place
and function of his phenomenology in this wider framework.
Heidegger recently
expressed the characteristic idea that every great thinker
"thinks only one single thought" (einen einzigen
Gedanken).1 There is no difficulty about discovering such a focal
idea in Heidegger's own thinking. One of its most instructive
expressions occurs in a seemingly minor place, the postcript to
What is Metaphysics? of 1934 and reads:
Man alone of all
existing things . . . experiences the wonder of all wonders:
that there are
things-in-being (dass Seiendes ist).2
There is perhaps no
better way to describe the basic difference between Heidegger's
and Husserl's fundamental purposes than to contrast this sentence
with a parallel statement in Husserl's writings: "The wonder
of all wonders is the pure ego and pure consciousness." (See
p. 87). Heidegger's fundamental wonder is objective Being,
Husserl's, subjective consciousness. The two problems are
sufficiently connected to account for the temporary coalition
between the two. But they are ultimately so far apart that Husserl
and Heidegger were bound to part company. This same fundamental
difference is also expressed in Heidegger's historical orientation
centering in Aristotle and, later, in Parmenides, toward whom
Husserl was particularly indifferent, compared with Husserl's
focal interest in Descartes, whom Heidegger opposes strenuously.
Heidegger himself
claims that he is the first thinker in the whole history of
philosophy (including phenomenology, as Husserl deduced with
amazement in his marginal comments to Sein und Zeit) to have
raised explicitly the question concerning the sense of Being.3 The
legitimacy of such a claim presupposes clarification of its
meaning.4 Heidegger is convinced
1 Was heisst
Denken? p. 20.
2 Was ist
Metaphysihf Sixth edition 1951, p. 42. See also Kant und das
Problem der Metaphysik, 2nd ed., p. 204: "We are familiar
with things in being - but being itself? Are we not always
attacked by dizziness (Schwindel) when we are to define or only to
grasp such matters?"
3 Einfuhrung in die
Metaphysik, p. 64.
4 It may be well to
recall that Heidegger's mystery of Being as such is not entirely
unknown to other thinkers, though not to philosophers in the
school sense.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
285
that man lives
usually in complete oblivion of the question of Being
(Seinsvergessenheit). In fact, in his "Brief uber den
Humanismus" he states that Sein und Zeit originated from the
fundamental experience (Grunderfahrung) of the general
forgetfulness of Being, an experience which would seem to be the
complement of the wonder of Being itself. It is this forgetfulness
of Being which Heidegger blames for the decline and crisis of
man's history on this planet.
But what precisely
is the sense of this question about Being (Sein; lately Heidegger
sometimes uses the old-fashioned spelling Seyn for emphasis) ? To
begin with, it is not Being itself, but the meaning (Sinn) of
Being which Heidegger wants to explore. At first sight one might
think that all that is involved is the discovery of the referents
of the word "Being" by a listing of its uses. As a
matter of fact, especially in his recently published Einfuhrung in
die Metaphysik, Heidegger goes to a considerable extent into the
etymology and even into the grammar of the word "sein."
However, beginning with Sein und Zeit, it becomes apparent, though
only gradually and indirectly, that "sense of Being"
("Sinn von Sein") means something much more specific.
For here "sense" is characterized mainly as the final
end (das Woraufhin) which makes a thing intelligible (p. 151).
This would seem to presuppose that Being as such has a definite
destination. Actually Heidegger tells us that only human existence
can be with or without meaning. Being has meaning only insofar as
it has import for a human being (Dasein),1 "protrudes"
into such a human being (sofern es in die Verstandlichkeit des
Daseins hereinsteht). It would appear, therefore, that the whole
question concerning the sense of Being has a rather limited scope,
since
A particularly
striking example can be found in the following passage from
Coleridge's The Friend:
Hast thou ever
raised thy mind to the consideration of existence, in and by
itself, as the mere act of existing? Hast thou ever said to
thyself thoughtfully, It is' heedless in that moment, whether it
were a man before thee, or a flower, or a grain of sand, - without
reference, in short, to this or that particular mode or form of
existence ? If thou hast attained to this, thou wilt have felt the
presence of a mystery, which must have fixed thy spirit in awe and
wonder. . . . Not to be is impossible:
to be,
incomprehensible. If thou hast mastered this intuition of absolute
existence, thou wilt have learned likewise that it was this, and
no other, which in the earlier ages seized the nobler minds, the
elect among men, with a sort of sacred horror. . . . The power
which evolved this idea of being, being in its essence, being
limitless, comprehending its own limits in its dilatation, aud
condensing itself into its own apparent mounds - how shall we name
it? ... (The Complete Works. New York, Harper, 1868, II, 463 f.).
1 I shall translate
Heidegger's peculiar use of the German word Dasein for the
thing-in-being called man (SZ p. 11), by "human being"
or "human existent."
286 THE GERMAN
PHASE
it affects only its
relation to man. However, in his later writings Heidegger seems to
have expanded the meaning of the question considerably. Thus the
introduction to the sixth edition of What is Metaphysics? (1951)
characterizes "sense" as the "accessible or open
area in which something can be understood." Also Sinn von
Sein and Wahrheit des Seins are here identified.1 Both expressions
seem to designate being in its capacity of being knowable.
A fuller
understanding of the significance of Heidegger's wonder also
presupposes a clear grasp of two related conceptions, that of the
"ontological difference" and that of "mode of
being" (Seinsart).
The ontological
difference (ontologische Differenz) is the distinction between
Sein and Seiendes. It is not quite easy to render this distinction
in English, especially in the absence of an unambiguous participle
equivalent to Seiendes; "what has being" or
"thing-in-being" (a suggestion by B. Q. Morgan) may be
the most adequate equivalent and less artificial than Ralph
Manheim's "essent." It is Heidegger's contention that
the neglect of this distinction is responsible for the increasing
failure not only of western philosophy but even of western
civilization. For they became more and more diverted from a
contemplation of Being to a study of, and finally to the technical
use and subjugation of, the things-in-being. Thus metaphysics,
science, and technology increasingly take the place of what should
properly be called ontology or the study of being. Specifically
metaphysics, as it has developed since the time of the early
Greeks, has become sidetracked almost completely into research on
the things-in-being, their natures and their uses.
How far is it
possible to study Being in independence of the things-in-being, as
Heidegger's demand for a fundamental revision of all previous
philosophy implies ? There is hardly any explicit answer to this
question in his published writings. The approach in Sein und Zeit,
however, suggests that it is primarily, if not exclusively, by the
analysis of a specific "thing-in-being," namely human
being (Dasein), that Being can be understood. Thus Being appears
to be a dependent attribute of things-in-being, an abstract
property or dependent part. Yet Heidegger
1 p. 17, see also
Vom Wesen der Wahrheit, Anmerkung (p. 26).
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
287
seems to assign it
much higher dignity, particularly in the later phases of his
philosophy. For here Being assumes an active role, revealing
itself to or hiding itself from thinking, and even determining the
fate of the things-in-being. Metaphorically Heidegger compares it
to a lightning or storm.1 In this respect, Being reminds one to
some extent of the Aristotelian and Thomist conception of
existentia as an active "form." One of the crucial
questions for Heidegger's philosophy of Being is how far not only
the "ontological difference," but this conception of the
place of Being in relation to the things-in-being is tenable.
Otherwise the whole emphasis on Being at the expense of the
things-in-being may amount to a case of "misplaced
concreteness" (Whitehead), i.e., of hypostatizing Being into
a separate entity.
Being as such,
however mysterious, may at first sight seem to be a rather
undifferentiated, if not monotonous, topic which hardly lends
itself to very extensive and illuminating study. What relieves
this possible uniformity is the fact that Being occurs in a
variety of forms (Seinsarten). Even before Heidegger, German
philosophers were in the habit of distinguishing, for instance,
between real being and ideal being (the being of mathematical
entities, of Platonic Ideas, or of values). Heidegger, to be sure,
rejects, or rather ignores, these earlier divisions. Instead, he
introduces such types of being as the mere occurrence of physical
objects (Vorhandensein), the "availability" of daily
utensils (Zuhandensein, literally: at-handedness), to which he
even assigns priority in our immediate experience, and the various
modes of being of man, the human being. Especially at the time of
Sein und Zeit the study of the modes of being in the human being
is the foundation of Heidegger's enterprise. In its course
Heidegger distinguishes between such constitutions of being
(Seinsverfassungen) as existence (Existenz), moods (Stimmungen),
concern (Sorge), or being-toward-death (Sein zum Tode). This
raises the question as to the difference between Heidegger's
concept of "mode of being" and that of other qualitative
charac-
1 Holzwege, p. 32;
Vortrage und Aufsatze p. 229. Karl Lowith, Heidegger, Denker in
duftiger Zeit (S. Fischer Verlag, 1953), p. 39, points out a
strange retreat from this position between the fourth edition of
What is Metaphysics? (1934), where Being is characterized as
independent of the things-in-being, and the fifth edition (1940),
where Heidegger states that Being never occurs without
things-in-being.
THE GERMAN PHASE
288
teristics of the
things-in-being. No explicit discussion of this fundamental
concept occurs in Heidegger's published writings.1 In its absence
it seems hard to justify his determined attempt to distinguish his
separation of an "ontological study of human existence"
confined to the modes of being (existentiale Analytik) from an
analytics of existence in all its qualitative features. This may
not invalidate the merits of Heidegger's accounts qua selective
analyses of certain features of human existence; but it makes it
dubious how far what he offers can be taken as an account of the
human mode of being and as indicative of being in general. Also,
the lack of a clear concept of mode of Being threatens to blur the
borderlines between Heidegger's "ontology" on the one
hand and science - anthropology in particular - on the other. The
clarification of the concept of mode of being would seem to be
crucial both for an understanding and for the ultimate evaluation
of Heidegger's enterprise.
While thus Being
(in contrast to the things-in-being) and the modes of being (in
contrast to the qualitative differences among the things-in-being)
form the central theme of Heidegger's thinking, at least a second
theme must be mentioned at the very start: time. It occurs as the
companion of Being in the title of Heidegger's central work.
Actually, it can be traced even in his writings before Sein und
Zeit. However, Heidegger's concern with time is not independent of
his primary theme, Being. For Being is to him essentially
temporal. The idea of a timeless or even eternal being is for him
illegitimate. Hence he also calls time in rather Husserlian but
indefinite terms "the possible horizon for an understanding
of Being," a formulation which implies that time is the most
promising frame of reference for the exploration of Being. But
Being is described not only as temporal but also as historical.
The full meaning of this characterization can be understood only
in the light of Heidegger's conception of history. Thus, by its
essence, Being has history, a history which is actually its own
doing as well as its undergoing.
If thus Being, in
contradistinction to the things-in-being, and time, as its frame
of reference, represent the persistent themes of Heidegger's
philosophizing, it seems somewhat surprising
1 For this problem
see also Alphonse de Waelhens, La Philosophic de Martin Heidegger
(Louvain, 1942), p. 309.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
289
that Heidegger's
thought, especially in his own eyes, has been subject to so many
misinterpretations. These are reflected particularly in the
various labels that have been attached to it. Specifically,
Heidegger's philosophy has been classified inter-changeably as
existentialism, philosophy of existence, philosophical
anthropology, metaphysics, or ontology. Heidegger himself has
protested against all these labels, in some cases from the very
beginning, in others only in the course of his later development,
but certainly only with limited success. The facts behind these
protests are briefly the following:
?. Heidegger has
always disclaimed to be an existentialist or even a philosopher of
existence. For human existence is to him neither the primary nor
the ultimate philosophical problem. The belief that his is a
philosophy of existence is actually the result of the
incompleteness of Sein und Zeit. For while Heidegger planned to
use his existential studies only as an entering wedge for his
major problem, the sense of Being in general, the non-appearance
of the later parts meant that only his analytics of existence was
available. The impressiveness of the published sections was
responsible for the fact that they became effective as studies of
human existence for their own sake, all the more since the
direction of Heidegger's next steps remained largely in the dark.
In other words, in the public eye Heidegger became an
existentialist despite himself.!
?. Heidegger has
always denied being a philosophical anthropologist after the
manner of Max Scheler. The impression that he is one has arisen
chiefly since his Kant book, which, even more than Sein und Zeit,
used the human being as its point of departure, and stressed
Kant's interest in man as an essentially metaphysics-minded being.
Even Husserl, as seen above, shared this view about Heidegger. But
while some aspects of philosophical anthropology were of
considerable interest to Heidegger during his middle period, he
certainly used them only as stepping stones on the way to
ontology.
?. Heidegger no
longer wants to be considered a metaphysician. The contrary
impression is due particularly to his Freiburg
1 See "Brief
fiber den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre van der Wahrheit, p.
73;
Letter to Jean Wahl
in Bulletin de la Societe Franfaise de philosophic XXXVII (1937),
p.193.
290 THE GERMAN
PHASE
inaugural address
of 1929 on "What is Metaphysics?," to his book on Kant
and the Problem of Metaphysics, and to his various lecture courses
on metaphysics, one of which was published under the old name as
late as 1953. However, after 1936 Heidegger began to announce the
need of an Uberwindung of metaphysics, a word which at first sight
seems to mean a conquest or overcoming of metaphysics, but which
Heidegger, who later came to regret this phrase as misleading, now
connects with the German word verwinden, meaning literally
"getting over a painful experience"; he thus implies
that metaphysics was a necessary phase in the history of Being.1
What is involved for Heidegger is the distinction between Being
and thing-in-being. He now holds metaphysics responsible for the
fateful preoccupation with the thing-in-being (Seiendes), instead
of with the fundamental theme of Being itself. Obviously,
Heidegger's protest against being called a metaphysician has to be
judged in the light of this peculiar definition and interpretation
of metaphysics.
?. But Heidegger
does not even want to be classed any longer as an ontologist. At
the time of Sein und Zeit, ontology, in contrast to metaphysics,
was characterized as the study of Being itself, and this study was
described as the only worthy subject of a phenomenological
philosophy. Its task was to be prepared for by a "fundamental
ontology" [Fundamentalontologie] of human being (Dasein). In
recent years, however, Heidegger has come to the conclusion that
the old term is too closely linked up with traditional metaphysics
to express his own meaning.
?. In fact, for
similar reasons, Heidegger now even rejects the very name
"philosophy." This name has become so hopelessly
discredited that it can no longer serve as the proper title for
Heidegger's new way of thinking. For "philosophy" is in
fact the "enemy" of thinking.2 The proper name for
Heidegger's philosophizing is Thought of Being (Denken des Seins).
Nevertheless it is still true even for him that such
"thinking" is based on "love of wisdom." 3
Thus in Heidegger's
own eyes Thought of Being is something utterly unique and
unclassifiable. We need not examine this
1 Vwtrage und
Aufsatze, p. 71 ff.
2 Holzwege, p. 247.
3 "Brief fiber
den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre van der Wahrheit, p. 119.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
291
implicit claim in
the present context. The question which concerns us is whether and
to what extent Heidegger's thinking can still be considered
phenomenology. Heidegger's silence on this point is certainly not
without significance. It is, as he intimated to me in
conversation, also related to his new aversion to all labels and
traditional classifications. This does not yet answer the
question, however, of how far not only the name
"phenomenology" but also the thing is absent or has
disappeared from his thought. It is this question which will
concern us now.
4. The Development
of Heidegger's Thought of Being
It is not only
Heidegger's 'Being' which has a history. This is also true of his
thinking about Being. For our purposes it will be important to
trace at least its major stages.
Even a merely
factual account, let alone a full understanding, of Heidegger's
intellectual history would presuppose much more biographical
material than is at present available, especially in the absence
of almost all autobiographical statements.! At least in this
respect Heidegger's reticence expresses the complete subordination
of his personality to the Seiche, the matter under consideration;
the first personal pronoun is unusually rare in Heidegger's
writing.
On the basis of
Heidegger's writings I shall distinguish three main periods in his
development relevant to the present enterprise. They are not
marked by abrupt breaks but rather by accelerated transformations.
There is a preparatory period in which Heidegger formulates his
basic theme, but is still in search of an adequate method of
attacking it. After the personal encounter with Husserl begins the
period of the maturation of Sein und Zeit, in which phenomenology
is the dominant methodo-logical principle. A third period is
characterized by the abandonment of the plan of Sein und Zeit, and
by a method which no longer emphasizes phenomenology.
1 Some indications
about the world of his early childhood can be found in a brief
little privately printed autobiographical sketch. Der Feldweg,
written after his sixtieth birthday. More significant data,
especially about his later philosophical development, can be
derived from the Brief uber den Humanismus and from the
chronological notes to the smaller essays and lectures published
since Sein und Zeit in front or in the back of these publications.
292 THE GERMAN
PHASE
a. preparatory
period - The Feldweg depicts Heidegger as the little son of the
sexton of St. Martin's church in Messkirch, Baden, "whose
hands often rubbed themselves hot in ringing the church bell ...
which had its peculiar relationship to time and temporality."
It is generally known that until 1911 Heidegger was first a novice
in a Jesuit seminary in Freiburg. As to the reasons for and the
form of his leaving, no authentic information is available. It is
not even known whether and to what extent his obvious move away
from the Catholic Church has led to a formal severance of his ties
with it. In any event, lately Heidegger has protested vigorously
against being classed as an atheist.
For one piece of
significant information about his philosophical development I am
indebted to Martin Heidegger personally:
The first
philosophical book, put into his hands casually by one of his
teachers at the Seminary, that made a lasting impression on his
mind was a doctoral dissertation on the multiple meanings of being
in Aristotle (Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seien-den nach
Aristoteles}; its author was Franz Brentano. It would be hard to
understand how this comparatively dry though most scholarly and
acute treatise could have affected Heidegger so deeply, unless the
question of the meaning of Being had already been simmering in him
at that early period.
Heidegger did his
Ph. D. work under the supervision of Hein-rich Rickert in
Freiburg. Even before its completion in 1913 he published a
critical survey on recent research in logic for a Catholic
magazine.1 It showed his familiarity with the whole range of
logical studies, including even the mathematical logic of Russell
and Whitehead. Husserl is mentioned repeatedly. Thus he writes:
We would like to
assign far-reaching significance to Husserl's circumspect and most
felicitously formulated investigations. For they really broke the
spell of psychologism and set in motion the clarification of
principles mentioned before (p. 466).
Besides, Husserl is
credited with having at the same time "founded"
phenomenology (the "study of the meaning of acts")
theoretically "and having done successful work in this
difficult
1 Literarische
Rundschau fur das katholische Deutschland XXXVIII (1912), 465-472,
517-524, 565-570.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
293
area" (p.
520). Heidegger's Ph.D. thesis dealt with the theory of judgment
according to psychologism, much in the free Neo-Kantian spirit of
the Freiburg philosophy of the time. The sections published in two
instalments in one of the leading philosophical periodicals of the
day1 show solid workmanship in the traditional style. Here
Heidegger identifies psychologistic elements not only in Wilhelm
Wundt but also in Franz Brentano and the later work of Theodor
Lipps. Husserl's critique of psychologism is mentioned only in
passing at the very start of the thesis in words almost identical
with those of the earlier survey.
The year 1912 also
sees the publication of a brief article, "Das
Realitatsproblem in der modernen Philosophic," in the
Catholic Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Gorresgesellschaft (XXV,
353-363) on the problem of reality in modern philosophy. Its main
ostensible purpose is a discussion of the critical realism of
Oswald Kulpe, the founder of the Wurzburg School, recommending
with minor reservations his epistemological work to the attention
of Aristotelian Scholastics, with whom Heidegger still seems to
identify himself. Perhaps even more important is the fact that the
article expresses for the first time Heidegger's concern with the
problem of Being, though in the traditional form of the
epistemological problem of reality. Against a cavalier dismissal
of this problem he insists that "the energetic liberation
(Sichlosringen) from the pressing deadweight (Bleilast) of a
supposed truism (Selbstverstandlichkeit) is a necessary condition
for a deeper realization of a task which calls for solution."
Also the article presents in detail the case against Humean and
Machian "conscientialism" (Konszientialismus) and
against Kantian phenomenalism in a way which makes Heidegger's
later tacit refusal to follow Husserl's phenomenological idealism
much more intelligible. Again Husserl's name appears only once in
a footnote in connection with the critique of psychologism in
logic.
The momentous
thesis which Heidegger submitted on the occasion of his admission
as a Privatdozent to the University of Freiburg in 1915 dealt on
the surface with a merely historical subject: Duns Scotus Doctrine
of Categories and Meanings.
1 Zeitschrift fur
Philosophic und philosophische Kritik CLV (1914), 148-172; CLVI
(1915), 41-78.
THE GERMAN PHASE
294
However, it is
noteworthy that in choosing a medieval thinker Heidegger picked
Duns Scotus, an "individual thinker with unmistakably modern
features" (p. 12), rather than Thomas Aquinas. The main basis
for his study was the so-called "Grammatical,
speculative!.," incidentally the very same text which had
attracted Charles Sanders Peirce on his way to his
"phenomeno-logical" studies of the categories, so much
so that he called himself a Scotist realist1 but which since then
has been traced back by Martin Grabmann - who gives high praise to
Heidegger's acute interpretation "in the terminology of
phenomenology" -to an otherwise unknown magister Thomas of
Erfurt.2
The contents of
Heidegger's seemingly rather specialized and remote study are of
much greater significance for his development than would appear
from the title. For it shows Heidegger in full transition not only
from scholastic philosophy but even from Rickert's transcendental
philosophy to Husserl, in fact not the Husserl of the Logische
Untersuchungen but of the Ideen. This is all the more remarkable
since at that time Heidegger was not yet in personal contact with
Husserl, although the concluding chapter may have been written
after Husserl's arrival in Freiburg. Actually, Heidegger's first
book shows more of the letter and the spirit of Husserl's early
phenomenology than any of his later writings. Besides, it reveals
in retrospect remarkable indications of Heidegger's entire later
development, although it still maintains connections with his
scholastic and theistic past.
It is true that on
its face the book carries a dedication to his main academic
teacher, Heinrich Rickert {in dankbarster Vereh-rung), and that it
often uses the language of his philosophy. Also, while intimating
considerable reservations, Heidegger still expresses great hopes
for the theory of value (Preface and p. 235), a term which he has
since then rejected with increasing vehemence. However, a glimpse
at the index of persons reveals that, while both Rickert and
Husserl are the most frequently quoted authors, there is even a
slight edge in favor of Husserl. In addition to that, Husserl's
decisive importance is stressed not only for the "pure logic
and theory of meanings" (p. 14 footnote
1 Charles K.
McKeon, "Peirce's Scotistic Realism" in Wiener, Philip
P. and Young, Frederic H. eds., Studies in the Philosophy of
Charles Sanders Peirce (Harvard University Press, 1952), pp.
238-50.
2 Mittelalterliches
Geistesleben (Munchen, Max Hueber, 1926), I, p. 116 ff.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
295
1), but also for
the "phenomenology of the noetic acts" (p. 102).
Intentionality in Duns Scotus is interpreted in Husserlian terms
(p. 130). Finally, Husserl's statements about "pure
consciousness" are cited as "giving a decisive preview
(Duchblick) of the richness of consciousness" and as
"destroying the often pronounced opinion about the emptiness
of consciousness in general" (p. 234, footnote).
These appraisals,
in combination with the extensive programmatic statements in the
introductory and concluding chapters, offer considerable clues as
to the reasons for Heidegger's turn toward a Husserlian
phenomenology, including even its emphasis on the subjective. In
his by no means uncritical account of medieval philosophy
Heidegger stresses its lack of methodical consciousness, its
missing urge and courage to ask questions independent of
authority, and the absence of a connection between abstract
principles and concrete life:
The Middle Ages
lack what makes the characteristic of the modern spirit: the
liberation of the subject from his ties with his environment, the
firm establishment in his own life. . . . For medieval man, the
stream of his peculiar life with its manifold entanglements,
diversions, and reflections in its varied and widely ramified
conditioning is mostly buried (verschutter), and is not recognized
as such. (p. 8)
True, Heidegger
makes a strong plea for the scholastic method, but only because it
includes "elements of phenomenological intuiting
(Betrachfung), perhaps more than any other" (p. 11). He also
points out that "at least insofar as it is permeated by the
genuine spirit of Aristotle" it is oriented toward
descriptive content rather than toward an empirical and genetic
explanation. But he also admits that its metaphysical way of
thinking cancels and even makes impossible the
"phenomenological reduction." Ultimately, Heidegger
stresses the need for intensified study of the scholastic
psychology, which is anything but psycho-logistic and is favorable
to a study of the phenomena of intentionality. Its theory of
meaning represents a good case of a going back to the subjective
act of signifying. Then he adds revealingly:
I consider the
philosophical, in fact the phenomenological exploration of the
mystical, ethico-theological, and ascetic literature of medieval
scholasticism as particularly urgent for decisive insight into the
basic character of scholastic psychology (p. 15).
296 THE GERMAN
PHASE
In this context
Heidegger reveals his plan of a study of Master Eckhart's
mysticism (p. 232 note).
Thus it is
strikingly clear that at the time of the thesis Husserl's emphasis
on subjectivity fitted in extremely well with Heidegger's
reservations against, and criticisms of, scholastic
philos-phizing. It provided for Heidegger the modern balance
against the traditional scholastic objectivism from which he came.
Presumably this was another reason why he had chosen Duns Scotus
as a symbol for his new enterprise.
Finally, the Duns
Scotus book foreshadows Heidegger's next phase by linking it with
his basic theme: Being. For in spite of the need of a subjective
logic to supplement the objective logic of scholasticism he
announces the ultimate need of a translogical metaphysics (the
word is printed in bold face) as the real optics (eigentliche
Optik) of philosophy, which is to go beyond the logical problems
of categories and meanings. For the first time a brief footnote
(p. 237) expresses the hope of an early, more detailed study about
Being, Value, and Negation, which is to include basic definitions
(prinzipielle Festsetzungen). Here is the nucleus of Sein und
Zeit. But there are also other signs of future developments, e.g.,
in the demand for a breakthrough through the totality of the
knowable to "true reality" and "real truth"
(p. 236).
The Duns Scotus
thesis also announces the theme of history. The "living
spirit," which is said to underlie the whole
logico-epistemological sphere with its problems of categories and
meanings, is said to be essentially historical. A historical
philosophy of this living spirit, as Heidegger seems to envisage
it in conclusion, would embrace both philosophy and mysticism. For
philosophy as a mere rationalistic structure is powerless, while
mysticism as mere irrationalistic Erieben is purposeless. It will
have to come to terms with the most powerful historical
Weltanschauung, that of Hegel, whose name ends the book, as a
motto from him had opened it.
Time and history
also form the subjects of Heidegger's inaugural lecture on
"The Concept of Time in Historiography." Here an even
more basic motif of Heidegger's later work is stated, although its
connection with the problem of Being is not yet visible to anyone
but the informed. For ostensibly it is only
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
297
historiography
which is under consideration. The time concept of history is,
however, contrasted sharply with that of natural science in a way
which shows Heidegger's familiarity with the science of Einstein
and Planck. As distinguished from the latter, historical time is
characterized as heterogeneous and qualitative, since condensed or
"crystallized" in the life of historical beings;
it is not identical
with the time of the mere chronicle of events. This too would seem
to point toward a more subjective type of time, as lived in human
existence. There is however no explicit reference to phenomenology
in this lecture.
Thus the basic
themes of Heidegger's phenomenology, Being, time, and history were
already formulated when Heidegger came in personal contact with
Husserl. Also, in addition to these goals, Heidegger had already
decided that a subjective approach in the manner of Husserl's
phenomenology was the most important extension of the
Aristotelian-scholastic methods needed for a successful approach
to these problems. But not until Heidegger took up full scale
lecturing after the end of the First World War was it manifest
that he wanted to be counted as a phenomeno-logist rather than as
a follower of Heinrich Rickert.
b. the
phenomenological period - I have already recorded the external
facts of the subsequent period in Heidegger's development as far
as his relationship to Husserl personally is concerned. But I have
not yet attempted to show their meaning in the light of
Heidegger's philosophical growth.
No adequate
information about the content of Heidegger's phenomenological
courses and seminars between his first Freiburg lectures and Sein
und Zeit is available. Hence there would be little point in
speculating about the meaning of their announced titles. Heidegger
himself indicates, however, that as early as 1919-20 he had
introduced his analysis of environment (Umweltanalyse) and his
"hermeneutics of factual existence" (Hermeneutik der
Faktizitat) in a course entitled "Selected Problems of Pure
Phenomenology." This makes it plain that from the very start
Heidegger took the liberty of interpreting and developing
phenomenology in his own way and for his own purposes. It also
stands to reason that his subsequent courses discussed further
themes of Sein und Zeit, which he started
298 THE GERMAN
PHASE
writing in 1922.1
Thus very soon Heidegger's phenomenology took on a very different
character from Husserl's and even from the one he seemed to be
advocating in the Duns Scotus book.
To trace these
differences in detail would require a complete analysis of Sein
und Zeit. I shall merely point out some of the major peculiarities
of this astonishing torso, comparing it particularly with
Husserl's approach.
oc. Perhaps the
most striking thing for anyone who comes to Sein und, Zeit from a
reading of Husserl's studies is the complete difference in
language and terminology. Even apart from the form of expression,
very rarely does there seem to be a similarity of concerns or
overlapping of topics. Specific references to Husserl's writings
are surprisingly rare, probably less in number than in the much
shorter Duns Scotus book, and they take up only minor items,
mostly from the Logische Untersuchungen. The reductions, both
eidetic and transcendental, Husserl's major concern since his
Ideen, are not even mentioned by name. However, apart from the
dedication, Husserl is given general credit in a paragraph which
states that
the following
investigations would not have been possible without the ground
laid by Husserl, whose Logische Untersuchungen meant the
breakthrough to phenomenology.
In a footnote to
this paragraph Heidegger also acknowledges his personal
indebtedness to Husserl, who had made possible his further
progress (einige Schritte vorwarts) by "familiarizing"
him "during his Freiburg apprenticeship (Lehrjahre) with the
most diverse areas of phenomenological research by intense
(ein-dringliche) personal guidance and by the freest possible
access to unpublished studies." (p. 38). However, a study of
Husserl's manuscripts published since then or otherwise known to
me provides little evidence that Husserl's unpublished writings
have influenced Heidegger's work except by way of challenge.2 What
is responsible for Heidegger's implicit rejection of some
1 Information given
on the cover of the record "Zum Atomzeitalter" (1955).
2 The reference to
Ideen II (Sein und Zeit, p. 47 footnote) represents a good example
of such stimulation. This raises the question of possible
influences in reverse from Heidegger on Husserl. If at all, these
have hardly been conscious ones. At most one might suspect that
such concepts as that of the Lebenswelt, or even the use of the
term "existential" in Husserl's later manuscripts, may
be an unconscious assimilation of some of Heidegger's motifs. See
also Alwin Dierner, Edmund Husserl, p. 65 f.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
299
of the basic
features of Husserl's later philosophizing ? Ultimately the answer
has to be given in the light of Heidegger's basic theme, Being,
and of the question how far Husserl's method of reduction could
have helped him in determining the meaning of this Being. As far
as the eidetic reduction to general essences is concerned, one
might perhaps think that Heidegger was heading for an
interpretation of Being as such, and hence that he could not
object to the eidetic method of generalizing abstraction. But one
of his first theses is that Being has not the nature of a genus
(p. 3). As a "transcendental" concept in the old
scholastic sense it "transcends" the customary
categories, hence no kind of generalization would be able to reach
it. Besides, Heidegger makes a special point of emphasizing that
Being, particularly in the case of human being, is fundamentally
individualized, something which is easily ignored in any
Platonizing approach.
As to the
phenomenological or "transcendental" reduction, even in
the form of mere bracketing of existence, the explanation is
perhaps even easier to find. For the reduction consists primarily
in suspending, at least temporarily, the question of whether any
given phenomenon has being. How can such a method help in
exploring the nature of Being ? Even though Husserl believes that
it ultimately can, it would seem rather strange to approach such a
problem by first looking away from it. Also it is certainly true
that in performing the reduction Husserl took little time to first
establish what it was that he suspended when he bracketed
"existence" and concentrated on "pure
phenomena" only. In other words, for Heidegger's undertaking
eidetic and transcendental phenomenology were at best useless, at
worst falsifying, when existence and being were at stake.
Apparently Heidegger tried on occasion to divert Husserl from his
stubborn insistence on the reductions, but to no avail. Yet, for
unstated reasons, he did not see fit to bring the issue out into
the open.
Nevertheless, there
are passages in Sein und Zeit where this difference nearly comes
to the surface. And at least on one such occasion Heidegger
intimates the deeper reasons for his avoidance of traditional
terminology, including that of Husserl's phenomenology with its
concepts of consciousness (Bewusstsein), subject, and personality.
As he puts it, they are all characterized by a "strange
insensitiveness" {Bedurfnislosigkeit) to the question
300 THE GERMAN
PHASE
of Being in the
things designated by the word "being" (in German the
word Bewusstsein actually includes the component
"being"). For although in comparison with Dilthey and
Bergson "the phenomenological interpretation of personality
is fundamentally more radical and transparent, it does not reach
the dimension of the being of Dasein." (p. 47). It is at this
point that Heidegger's new hermeneutic phenomenology is ready to
step in.
Thus emphasizing
the differences in approach and development between Sein und Zeit
and Husserl's thought should of course not minimize the common
themes and perspectives which a more penetrating study would be
able to bring to the surface. Even though Heidegger avoids
demonstratively such terms as "intentionality," the
phenomenon it designates is omnipresent in his concept of
"being-in-the world." Even more obvious is the common
interest in such topics as "world" and "time."
This is certainly more than a coincidence. But without further
evidence than the texts there is very little chance to determine
the kind and amount of influences.
P. In spite of the
obvious differences, even Heidegger's new phenomenology shared
with Husserl's version at least the general area of departure,
namely man himself, if not in the form of the conscious subject,
at least in that of human being (Dasein). For the strategy of Sein
und Zeit consists in an attack upon the meaning of Being by way of
an analysis of the being of man, inasmuch as he is the privileged
entity who is concerned about his being and has thus a certain
understanding of Being, however defective, from the very start.
Man is thus fundamentally "ontological," i.e., thinking
about the "on" (being). So the plan of Sein und Zeit in
its first half provides for an analysis of this human being. This
half is subdivided into three sections, of which only two have
been published, the first being a preparatory analysis of human
being for its ontological structure, the second giving a
fundamental (urs-prungliche) analysis of this being in its
relation to temporality. The third section, whose publication has
now been abandoned for good, was to furnish the transition from
human being and human temporality to time and Being itself; here
human being was no longer to function as the exclusive clue to
Being. The second half of the work, also abandoned, was to be
reserved for a "phenomenological destruction" of the
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
301
history of ontology
based on the analysis of temporality, and was presumably meant to
supply a confirmation of the conclusions of the systematic first
half by means of a critical interpretation of three decisive
chapters of the history of philosophy.
This approach,
beginning from human being and leading to Being itself, reflects
at least to some extent Husserl's primary emphasis on
subjectivity, as developed in the Ideen and in his later writings.
It differs from these, however, by the substitution of human being
for pure consciousness. What is the real meaning of this
substitution, and what is the relationship between these two
conceptions? Here lies perhaps the decisive difference between
Husserl's and Heidegger's phenomenologies.
Heidegger's concept
of human being is closely linked up with his concept of existence,
although strictly speaking existence (i.e., the "possibility
of being or not being oneself") is only one of several basic
features of human being. It is at this point that Heidegger's
phenomenology makes its momentous and fateful contact with the
philosophy of existence, which, going beyond Heidegger's own
intentions, has since led almost to an identification of
phenomenology and existentialism. There is thus far no way of
telling what led Heidegger to the adoption of his new concept of
existence, which differs basically from the scholastic use
(opposed to essence), as it is found even in Heidegger's Duns
Scotus book. It seems likely that the study of Kierkegaard (which
became widespread in Germany after the First World War and which
was promoted further by Jaspers' account of him, even before
Jaspers himself had fully developed his philosophy of existence)
had a good deal to do with it.1
But even more
important is an understanding of the purpose of Heidegger's
analysis of existence. For Heidegger wants it to be understood
that this analysis is not to be a full-fledged study of human
existence in the sense of Jaspers' philosophy, for which Heidegger
uses the German adjective "' existentiell." His own
analysis is meant to be "existential," a new coinage in
German, which is supposed to convey the idea that human existence
is to be studied only for its "categories," not for its
what or nature,
1 See, e.g., Sein
und Zeit, p. 338. Actually, Kierkegaard's name appears only three
times and relatively late in Sein und Zeit, and then merely in an
incidental manner (pp. 190, 235 note, 338).
302 THE GERMAN
PHASE
since this is all
that is needed for the proposed approach to Being in general. To
be sure. Being for Heidegger is the decisive part of human being,
so much so that he is not even sure whether there is an essence of
man over and above his being: For "The essence of human being
lies in existence" (p. 42). In view of this, one may well
doubt whether there would be anything left for a philosophy of
existence after Heidegger's analytics of existence had carried out
its task. Existence, as Heidegger sees it, is anyhow a
non-theoretical affair, which can be handled only by actual
existing, not by any kind of theoretical analysis (p. 12).
But this does not
yet explain Heidegger's reason for replacing consciousness by
human being. Heidegger's answer is that Husserl's conscious ego,
as well "as that of Descartes, leaves the question of the
being of such consciousness completely unanswered.1 This may seem
somewhat surprising since Husserl, although he
"brackets" the being of the whole
"transcendent" world, insists all the more on the
"absolute," "apodictic," and indubitable being
of pure consciousness, without, to be sure, elaborating on what
such absolute being involves. What Heidegger seems to be missing
must be the discussion of the "meaning" of being as he
himself supplies it, something which has to do with the objective
of consciousness in its constitutive functions. Though in his last
stage Husserl seems to have considered such problems explicitly
under the heading of teleology, this certainly does not amount to
anything comparable to Heidegger analytics of human being.
While Heidegger
thus believes he is even more radical than Husserl himself with
his return to the transcendental ego, he is in another sense
unwilling to go so far. Perhaps this can best be illustrated from
Heidegger's comments on the following sentence in Husserl's draft
of the Encyclopaedia Britannica article: "If I carry out the
(transcendental) reduction for myself, I am not a human ego."
In his comment Heidegger underlines "I am" and
"not" and adds, "or perhaps I am precisely that, in
its most specific, most amazing ('wundersamst') existential
possibility." In the margin he also asks: "Why not?
Isn't this activity a
1 Sein und Zeit,
pp. 46, 207 f. This point is also made with great emphasis in
Heidegger's comments on Husserl's Encyclopaedia, Britannica
article (Tijdschrift voor Philosophic, XII, p. 274).
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
303
potentiality of
man.. . ?" Here is the deepest root of the growing
disagreement: For Husserl, man is an entity constituted by his
consciousness; for Heidegger, consciousness, even in its
sublimated phenomenological form, is conversely an activity of
man, constituted by him. Without presuming to rule on the merits
of the case, I submit that the ultimate difference is based on a
difference of focus: Husserl is interested primarily in the
epistemo-logical aspect (How do we know about man?), Heidegger in
the "ontic" angle (What is Being and what are the
foundations for philosophizing and phenomenologizing in the midst
of it?). Heidegger undertakes to shift the center of gravity of
phenomenology by making human being, rather than consciousness,
its hinge. For those who do not share his ontological concern,
this amounts indeed to an entirely new phenomenology with an
anthropological foundation. The phenomenology of Sein und Zeit is
still subjectivistic to the extent that it makes man its point of
departure. But this is certainly no longer a transcendental
subjectivity in Husserl's sense.
y. Still another
point about Heidegger's position in Sein und Zeit deserves
discussion here, especially in view of the fact that Heidegger
by-passes Husserl's method of reduction: his attitude toward
phenomenological or transcendental idealism.
Husserl's marginal
notes to Sein und Zeit make it plain that to him Heidegger's
philosophy appeared to be nothing but another type of realism,
related even to the old scholastic realism of Thomas Aquinas, from
whom, he thought, Heidegger had not yet freed himself completely.
Heidegger himself certainly does not acknowledge any such
commitments, but rather claims that his new approach unhinges the
whole stalemated problem of realism and idealism, which relates
the issue to the question of dependence upon consciousness, rather
than upon human being. But apart from rejecting Husserl's point of
reference Heidegger admits a realistic element in his concept of
"Erschlossenheit," i.e., literally, the unlockedness or
accessibility in the things as encountered in our world. He
opposes realism only insofar as it is supposed to imply the
reducibility of Being to things-in-being (p. 21 Of.) -hardly one
of the customary interpretations of realism. A few pages later he
denies specifically that reality, in the sense of physical and
cultural things, is dependent upon human being.
304 THE GERMAN
PHASE
He does assert,
however, that "only as long as there is human being, i.e.,
the ontic possibility of understanding of being, is there
{"es gibt") such a thing as "Being." Unless
the "es gibt" is interpreted in a Pickwickian sense,
this certainly sounds like idealism at its strongest. It should be
added, however, that since then Heidegger has interpreted this
statement in the sense that "only as long as human being
is," i.e., man as the "clearing" of Being (die
Lichtung des Seins), does Being hand itself over (ubereignet sick)
to man.1 Hence the "es gibt" must have meant literally
"giving itself," not "occurring," in which
case being might well precede and survive the
"gift-stage."
Clearly, this
cannot be considered a satisfactory adaptation of Husserl's
transcendental idealism. Heidegger's later development completely
removes the seeming traces of the transcendental idealism of this
period.
S. The above
discussion of Sein und Zeit merely means to bring out aspects that
have bearing on Heidegger's general development. Hence, instead of
the problematical attempt to summarize its other theses, of which
I shall select later those that illustrate his phenomenological
method, I shall simply try to indicate the stage at which
Heidegger leaves his reader at the end of the published two
sections of the first half of the work.
The preparatory
analysis of human being in the first section, starting from man's
everyday existence, had led to a determination of the
"meaning of Being" (Sinn des Seins) of human being for
which Heidegger uses the term Sorge (concern). The second section
had attempted an interpretation of human being as a whole by
introducing the element of time in the form of temporality, i.e.,
the time-structure of our existing. In fact, temporality was now
called the "meaning" (Sinn) of concern (Sorge), which
had previously been called the being of human being. Thus the
published sections of the work reach at least Heidegger's first
objective: the determination of the meaning of one type of Being,
the Being of the potentially most revealing thing-in-being, man.
This leaves other types of being undetermined. More important, it
leaves the climactic question of the meaning of Being in general
still unanswered, much as one can surmise that the temporality of
human being was meant to be
1 "Brief fiber
den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre van der Wahrheit, p. 83.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
305
the bridge to
"Time and Being," the announced topic for section III.
The last pages of the published part leave the reader with a
string of questions, which may at first seem to be merely
rhetorical, aimed at intensifying the reader's expectation. In
retrospect, however, one notices certain ominous undertones of
indecision as to the best possible way to attack the major
question. In fact, we are told in the end that there is no chance
of settling the controversy about the interpretation of Being,
since thus far it has not even been stirred up (entfacht).
But if Sein und
Zeit is incomplete, one might at least think of it as a complete
and final treatment of a more limited subject with the more
appropriate title "Human Being and Temporality" (Dasein
und Zeitlichkeit, actually the title of section II). The
difficulty with such a restrictive interpretation is that too
often in the development of these sections we are told to wait for
the final denouement of points discussed merely in a preliminary
fashion. In view of this fact the question arises whether
Heidegger's later work can in some way provide the missing
keystone for the impressive arch which he built in Sein und Zeit.
Heidegger's
contribution to the Husserl-Festschrift of 1929, "Vom Wesen
des Grundes," is ostensibly not directly related to Sein und
Zeit. It is not easy to determine the exact place of this study,
which is unusually compact and far from easy to interpret. It
certainly does not elucidate the meaning of 'ground' in any
customary sense. The essay follows the pattern of Sein und Zeit,
inasmuch as it approaches the problem of ground by way of the
study of Dasein, particularly in the form of what Heidegger i;
now calls
"transcendence," namely the self-transcendence of man in
the direction of a world. This transcendence itself is traced back
to man's freedom, which might make one think that Heidegger wants
to derive the world from a free act of the human being, which
would amount to a kind of existential idealism. But this is not
the case. For freedom, as Heidegger soon adds, consists,
paradoxically enough, in letting the world take its own course (W
altenlassen), which sounds more like an act of giving freedom than
of having it. The final analysis of the free act of grounding
reveals human being as not only projecting the world
(Weltentwurf), but as having been taken over by the world
(Eingenommensein). In fact, human being is now conceived of as
306 THE GERMAN
PHASE
being in the midst
of being other than human being. Thus, while human being still
appears as the primary access to such concepts as
"ground" and "being," it is now ontologically
imbedded in being and certainly not equipped with any kind of
constitutive function and superiority as it is in transcendental
idealism.1
About one year
after his return to Freiburg Heidegger delivered his celebrated
and perhaps most widely quoted inaugural lecture, "What is
Metaphysics ?" Ostensibly it still advocates a revival of
metaphysics, which is to include the exploration of the ground of
the things-in-being. Indeed, the postscript of 1934, and even more
the introduction of 1951, show to how many misinterpretations his
formulation of the basic question of metaphysics ("Why is
there something and not rather nothing at all?") had given
rise. The impression was certainly defensible that Heidegger was
on the way to a reconstruction of metaphysics in its most
comprehensive sense, rather than to its re-orientation around the
problem of Being in contrast to the things-in-being. This, among
other things, may account for his later efforts at
"overcoming" or "getting over" metaphysics.
The lecture itself
fits into the approach of Sein und Zeit, in its move from human
being to Being. But it views the problem of Being from a new side,
namely from its contrast to nothingness. According to Heidegger,
nothingness itself, puzzling though it is, becomes accessible in
the fundamental experience (Grund-erfahrung) of human existence
called anxiety, in which the things-in-being seem to retreat or
flee away from us. To Heidegger this metaphysical experience is
actually a part of human being, in fact the fundamental event in
human experience, so much so that he even states that metaphysics
is human being itself. Thus it is still the subject in the form of
man, with his questions and experiences, that seems to supply the
privileged approach to Being as such.
In 1929 Heidegger
published his third book, Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik. To
some extent this may be considered as an installment of the
projected first section of the second half of Sein und Zeit, which
was to furnish a "phenomenological destruction" of the
three major ontologies that Heidegger
1 About the
"misleadingness" of this essay as seemingly dealing with
the metaphysics of things-in-being, see Der Satz vom Grunde
(1957), p. 84.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
307
considered to be
the main obstacles to his fresh start. But as it stands, the book
seems to have been conceived independently and can be considered
as a kind of historical prolegomena to Sein und Zeit as a whole.
It is the first of those historical interpretations which in a
unique way combine painstaking documentation in securing the
original texts with admitted violence in their use. It is also a
first example in Heidegger's writing of the form of dialogue
between himself and the great philosophers of the past which is so
characteristic of Heidegger's later philosophizing.
Seen in a wider
context, the Kant book means simply an indirect corroboration and
reinforcement of Heidegger's main plea in Sein und Zeit, the need
of a "fundamental ontology" of human being focused on
the phenomenon of temporality as the foundation of a genuine
philosophy and metaphysics. To this extent it does not represent
any significant shift in Heidegger's development. Nevertheless it
is a highly instructive piece, particularly if compared with a
fuller and less forced view of Kantian philosophy.
Revealing, for
instance, is the interpretation of the Critique of Pure Reason as
an attempt to lay the foundations of a metaphysics based on the
nature of man. Man is now defined not as an a priori ideal
subject, however empirically imperfect, but as finite, chiefly
because his knowledge is primarily Anschauung -the latter a view
well in line with phenomenology, but perhaps questionable in the
light of Kant's view of the relation between Anschauung and
Begriff - and because this Anschauung is non-creative and
dependent on something already in existence (p. 31), hence
derivative - a view which indicates again the realistic element in
Heidegger, if not in Kant.
Another distinctive
feature of Heidegger's interpretation of Kant is the decisive
weight he attaches to the synthetic imagination (Einbildungskraft)
as the root of the synthesis between intuition and thought,
particularly in connection with the problem of the doctrine of the
transcendental schema. Equally important is the role given to time
for an understanding of the workings of the synthetic imagination.
But the most
important aspect of the book is the explanation Heidegger gives
for the disappearance of the synthetic imagination from the second
edition of the Critique of Pure Reason.
308 THE GERMAN
PHASE
For Heidegger sees
in it a sign of Kant's retreat (Zuruckweichen) from the
implications of his own approach: he cannot bear the realization
of the subjective character of the subject (p. 194). "To
question one's way (Hineinfragen) into the subjectivity of the
subject, the 'subjective deduction,' leads into darkness." In
the attempt to lay a subjective foundation for the Critique of
Pure Reason Kant had actually undermined it: the foundations
threaten to cave in and to reveal the abyss (Abgrund) of
metaphysics. Regardless of how clear and convincing this
interpretation is, one of the implications of Heidegger's
concluding critique of Kant's approach is that it indirectly
reveals the failure of the subjective approach, so basic to
Husserl's phenomenology of subjectivity, which had led Husserl to
increasing interest in and admiration for Kant. To Heidegger,
subjectivism was now a failure, in view of the essential
finiteness of man, i.e., the dependence of his Anschauung on
powers not in himself. And Kant's failure spelled Husserl's
failure as well.
Finally, there is
the fact that the book, dedicated to the memory of Max Scheler,
contains a discussion of Scheler's idea of a philosophical
anthropology as an alternative foundation for metaphysics. This is
rejected in favor of the "fundamental ontology" of Sein
und Zeit, which alone is said to make possible an understanding of
the finiteness of man. Thus, although there are indications of
further developments in Heidegger's thought, the fundamental
approach to Being through human being remains unchanged. Yet no
basic progress beyond Sein und Zeit is apparent from Heidegger's
publications during the twenties.
After 1929 the
roster of Heidegger's publications shows another conspicuous gap.
The early thirties were the period of his temporary but intense
involvement in the affairs of the Nazi regime. In the present
context his political expectations and early disillusionment are
without immediate significance. What is significant, however, is
the fact of his association with a political movement as
activistic and violent as Nazism. It is true that authentic
existence, as Heidegger conceived of it at the time, called for
resoluteness (Entschlossenheit, a word which in customary German
has exclusively voluntaristic connotations). But beyond the
meaning of an orientation toward death (Sein zum
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
309
Tode), Sein und
Zeit had failed to define the kind of life this would spell.1
Quite possibly
during these years Heidegger had the strange illusion that not
only could his own philosophy assimilate some of the Nazi ideology
but also that he could offer the latter a more adequate philosophy
than Alfred Rosenberg's "Myth of the Twentieth Century."
The grotesqueness of this error does not make the spectacle of
this episode any more edifying.
The only separate
publication from this period is Heidegger's Pectoral Address of
1933, entitled oddly enough "The Self-assertion of the German
University." The revealing part about it is the
reinterpretation of science in the context of the new political
pattern as he conceived of it. The address contains Heidegger's
supreme appeal to the will as the lever for shaping man's destiny
in his universe and, in the case of science, for unlocking the
essence of all things. What is more, the universe now appears so
antagonistic to man that this address expresses the closest
approximation to explicit atheism that can be found anywhere in
Heidegger's writings.2 In a sense this speech, together with
similar utterances from this period, represents the high watermark
and possibly the turning point of Heidegger's trust in the
capacity of human being to force Being to surrender its secret.
Nietzsche's will-to-power is its symbolic expression. The failure
of Heidegger's excursion into the political world spells not only
the end of his activism but also of his trust in human being and
the powers of subjectivity as embodied in the will.
c. under the sign
of Holderlin - To what extent has there been a break in
Heidegger's thinking since Sein und
1 There is a
characteristic story of a student of Heidegger who emerged from
one of his lectures with the exclamation: "I am resolved:
Only I am not sure on what.*' See K. Lowith, "Les
Implications politiques de la philosophic d'existence de
Heidegger" in Les Temps Modernes II (1946), 347.
2 "If that is
true which Friedrich Nietzsche, the last German Philosopher who
passionately sought God, said, namely that 'God is dead' - if we
have to accept seriously the forsakenness of modern man in the
midst of the things-in-being . . . then the perseverance of the
Greeks before the existing world, initially in the spirit of
admiration, now becomes a completely unsheltered exposure to the
hidden and uncertain, i.e., the questionable." Science now
becomes an "inquiring, unsheltered perseverance {Standhalten}
in the midst of the uncertainty of the things-in-being as a
whole" (p. 12 f.). By contrast, Heidegger's reinterpretation
of Nietzsche in 1943 {Holzieege 1950, p. 293 ff.) leaves us wholly
uncertain as to his own position. It is perhaps not insignificant
that Sartre, who labelled Heidegger an atheist, was in Freiburg
around the time of this Pectoral Address.
THE GERMAN PHASE
310
Zeit and, more
particularly, since the end of his involvement in politics ?
Certain changes, such as the disappearance of the term
phenomenology, are manifest. But do they justify the belief that
Heidegger came to reverse himself? The case for such an
interpretation has been stated most clearly by as informed a
critic as Karl Lowith.1 However, Heidegger himself asserts that
there is no such break. Certainly he has not repudiated Sein und
Zeit, but keeps referring to it, as if he considered it his most
permanent and presumably his greatest achievement.
I shall begin by
presenting the concrete evidence for the view that there have been
serious shifts in Heidegger's thinking, sufficient to set his
later period apart from what was described earlier.
There is, first of
all, the postponement and apparently now the abandonment of the
plan of publishing the missing parts of Sein und Zeit. Heidegger's
own explanation for this reversal is that the third section of the
first half of Sein und Zeit, which, under the title of "Zeit
und Sein," was to furnish the final answer to the question of
the meaning of Being, was "held back" (hence, it seems
to have existed) at the time of the publication of the first
sections "because thinking failed in the attempt to express
adequately the turning (Kehre) - from 'Sein und Zeit' to 'Zeit und
Sein' - and did not reach its goal by using the language of
metaphysics." 2 It is not exactly easy to appraise the
difficulties for which language alone is held responsible here.
But it is hardly insignificant that what Heidegger was most
worried about in the context of this quotation is the danger of a
subjectivistic interpretation of Sein und Zeit. Thus, he is
anxious to stress the need of a thinking that "leaves behind
subjectivity" and the idea of "achievements of
subjectivity" (p. 69 f.), which seemed to be suggested
particularly by the concept of an existential project (Entwurf)
introduced in connection with the hermeneutics of human being.
Heidegger adds that
the lecture Of the Essence of Truth "conceived and read in
1930 but not printed until 1943," throws a "certain
light" on the thinking of his decisive "turn" in
Sein und Zeit to Time and Being. The modesty of this claim and in
fact
1 Heidegger, Denker
in durftiger Zeit, Chapter I.
2 "Brief fiber
den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre van der Wahrheit, p. 72.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
311
the delay in the
publication of the lecture is possibly explained by a note at its
very end to the effect that it was to be supplemented by a second
lecture "Of the Truth of Essence": But "this
lecture miscarried (misslang) for reasons now hinted at in the
letter Uber den Humanismus." Since no specific reference to
the lecture occurs in the letter, it may be inferred that it was
again the inadequacy of the language of metaphysics which was at
the root of this second failure.
These two striking
admissions of change of plan and failure must be taken together
with the evidence afforded by Heidegger's actual publications in
the years since 1933. These consist almost exclusively of lectures
and smaller essays, which in recent years (since 1950) have been
combined in book form. They also include the edition of some
important courses and even a little volume of poetry and aphorisms
(Von der Erfahrung des Denkens). There is however at present no
promise of a book which could take the place of the missing parts
of Sein und Zeit.
On the other hand,
there is a surprising widening in Heidegger's range of interests.
There is particularly a seemingly sudden new interest in fine art,
music, and particularly in poetry, which was conspicuous by its
absence in the earlier period. This became manifest almost
abruptly after the end of Heidegger's excursion into politics, and
expressed itself particularly in the sequence of his commentaries
on some relatively neglected and difficult poems of Holderlin, the
Hellenizing German Romantic, on Rilke (whom he rejects in spite of
obvious affinities), and on the recent poet Georg Trakl. Besides,
Heidegger reveals an intense interest in the nature and meaning of
technology. This increased range of topics, however, by no means
indicates an abandonment of his original concern, rather its
pursuit into new areas.
The present context
does not call for a detailed account of all these efforts but
merely for an attempt to point out some of the pervading features
and results of this ongoing period, sufficient to determine its
relationship to the earlier outspokenly phenome-nological phase in
Heidegger's development.
To begin with more
external characteristics, Heidegger's writings of this period are
not only shorter but more rounded within their more limited scope.
They show a deliberate attempt to avoid the traditional
terminology of philosophy, yet try all
THE GERMAN PHASE
312
the harder to
squeeze all the juices of literal meaning out of the old word
shells, and sometimes even to instill new life into them. Many
terms and concepts, especially the more technical ones, disappear
from his vocabulary. Others are reinterpreted and even re-spelled,
such as existence (now: Ek-sistenz) or Sein (often:
Seyn), and some are
added, such as Ge-Stell for the products of technology, or dingen
as the mode of being of the "thing" (Ding). On the
whole, the fewer new terms Heidegger uses, the more he overloads
the existing ones. The style is less involved, and especially the
lectures display a clarity of organization and even of diction
which makes them perhaps the best introduction to Heidegger's
entire thought. One senses an intensified need for communication
and contact .with the audience, especially in the lectures. This
does not mean that their sense is easy to assimilate. Even now
there is very little attempt to prove points in any traditional
sense of the word by "for's" and "because's."
"Nothing can be proved in this area, but some things can be
shown." 1 One does not even notice a sustained effort to show
them. Instead, we find mostly the bare pronouncement of a
"truth" which, if it does not ask to be accepted on the
writer's say-so, makes high demands on the reader's sympathetic
efforts at understanding and verification.
Perhaps the most
startling change in the content of Heidegger's later thought is
that Being, the distant goal of Sein und Zeit, suddenly appears to
be so close and manifest that hardly any special approach or
method seems to be needed to discover it, once we have stopped
running away from it. After the 438 pages of Sein und Zeit, which
constantly stressed our utter ignorance of the meaning of being,
in fact our unawareness of the question, and which made Being seem
the darkest possible mystery, to be approached via human being and
even via the experience of nothingness, it now appears that Being
is essentially open and unconcealed all the time and that we have
direct access to it, provided we do not forget it. Yet even
Heidegger says that we live in, and in fact are nothing but, a
"clearing" (Lichtung) in the midst of Being, which seems
to imply that around this clearing Being is still a dark jungle.
What is more, it is not given to human being or thinking to force
its way into Being, but it is
1 Identitat und
Differenz, p. 10.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
313
primarily Being
itself which reveals itself to thinking by its own initiative, its
speaking to us (Zuspruch). Man can do nothing but either resist or
accept it in "mellow tranquillity" (Gelassenheit der
Milde). It is significant that in this context Heidegger often
uses a German expression which comes very close to the equivalent
of grace: Huld, i.e., graciousness, or Gunst, i.e., favor of
Being.
The clearest
expression of this new interpretation of thinking as mostly
receptive is to be found in Heidegger's lecture course on Was
heisst Denken? It is for this reason also that Heidegger now calls
man, in a language reminding one of Rilke, the
"shepherd" or "guardian" of Being, whose main
function it is to watch "the house of Being," namely
language. "Was heisst Denken?" distinguishes four senses
of the question about the meaning of thinking, based upon various
meanings of the word "heissen" in German, which
comprises "meaning" and "bidding." To
Heidegger the most important of these meanings is "What bids
us to think?" The answer to this is none other than: Being
itself. Thinking thus loses its character of a spontaneous
activity and consists instead in an acceptance and listening to
the voice of Being.
It is part of the
same pattern that thinking now moves into the immediate
neighborhood of poetry. And while Heidegger still distinguishes
between the thinker who "says" Being and the poet who
"names" the Holy,1 the latter is certainly not the
inferior, and at times it would even seem the superior, of the
thinker. There are actually places where even thinking appears as
one of the offshoots of poetry. It needs to keep close to poetry,
which is its "good" and hence its healthy (heilsam)
danger, as opposed to itself, its "evil" danger, and to
philosophy, its "bad" danger. 2
It is obvious that
this type of thinking leaves little room for anything like a
method. Actually, logic in Heidegger's new sense means something
entirely different from the traditional logic, in which he sees
practically nothing but the precursor of "Logistik" or
mathematical logic, another branch of modern technology. It is
obvious that this must also affect the idea of phenome-
' Was ist
Metaphysik? Nachwort, p. 46. 2 A us der Erfahrung des Denhens, p.
15.
314 THE GERMAN
PHASE
nology as a
philosophical method which approaches its object in the spirit of
research. For no method is called upon to enforce the revelation
of truth, at best it can prepare the way of truth in the thinker.
One other element
in Heidegger's later period, closely related to this
Being-centered approach and of considerable importance for his new
attitude toward phenomenology, is his attack on subjectivism and
subjectivity in philosophy. This should be contrasted with his
plea for the need of subjective studies as a supplement to the
objective logic of the categories in the Duns Scotus book.1 Sein
und Zeit represented an effort to substitute human being for the
subject of pure consciousness, but it still approached Being from
the same direction. Now "not only every kind of anthropology
and every subjectivity in the sense of man as a subject has been
left behind, as it was already in Sein und Zeit ... but the way of
the lecture undertakes to think by beginning from this new ground
(the Da-sein)." 2 Da-sein in this new sense, in which the
hyphen makes the first syllable emphatic, is no longer human
existence in its relation to the world but rather to what is
there, i.e.. Being in its openness or "truth," something
into which man can enter.3
Perhaps Heidegger's
strongest condemnation of subjectivism develops out of his
critical discussion of Nietzsche's philosophizing. For he sees in
it an extension of Descartes' way of thinking. Descartes' ego
cogito, which is also Husserl's foundation stone, becomes to
Heidegger the symbol of the modern age. It represents an
insurrection against Being as such, converting all things-in-being
into objects for a subject and ultimately sucking them into
subjectivity. As a result they are reduced to mere perspectives
under the control of the value decisions of the will-to-power.4 In
spite of his high regard for Nietzsche as a thinker, Heidegger
thus sees in him the climax in the revolt of subjectivism.
1 "Without
taking account of 'subjective logic' it does not even make sense
to talk about immanent and transcending {"transeunt"}
validity. ... Objectivity (Gegenstdndlichkeit) makes sense only
for a predicating subject, without which it will never be possible
to bring out the full meaning of what is meant by validity
(Geltung). (Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus,
pp. 234 ff.).
2 Vom Wesen der
Wahrheit, p. 27.
a Was ist
Metaphysik? Einleitung (1951), p. 13.
4 Holzwege, p. 241.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
315
A case may be made
for the view that Heidegger himself reversed his attitude toward
the will during the period of his Nazi involvement. At first the
will to a vaguely conceived national destiny had seemed to him
also the guide to Being. His disillusionment with this final
outburst of the will, coupled with his return to a poet as
contemplative as Holdedin, may well have something to do with his
final repudiation of all types of subjectivism. No wonder the turn
away from phenomenology, at first only in the form of a rejection
of Husserl's transcendental subjectivism, now confirmed his
disinterest in any kind of subject-centered approach.
One other change
around this time made likewise for Heidegger's latest disinterest
in phenomenology. Up to the time of his Rectoral Address of 1934,
Heidegger had never displayed any fundamental reservations or
objections to the idea of science in the German sense of the word,
which comprises both the natural sciences and the social and
historical studies (Geisteswissenschaften). Nor did he object to
Husserl's idea of philosophy as a rigorous science. He used to
insist that the special sciences are dependent branches of
philosophy, and that, if completely emancipated from philosophy,
they become degenerations of philosophy. But even in the address
of 1933 science appears as one of the highest possibilities of
human existence. Besides, Heidegger has exerted a highly
stimulating influence on several scientific studies, chiefly the
sciences of man.1
This attitude
toward science changes with Holzwege, where for the first time
science as such comes under attack. Heidegger now states that in
science, as contrasted with art, no original truth is found but
merely the development of what is already known (p. 50). An even
more serious stricture against science follows as a result of
Heidegger's attack on modern technology, in which he sees nothing
but an outgrowth of the modern metaphysics of the will, an attack
which is related to Heidegger's earlier analysis of the things of
our daily environment by such concepts as utensil (Zeug). Thus
modern science, along with the totalitarian state, is interpreted
as a necessary consequence of modern
1 See especially M.
Heideggers Einfluss auf die Wissenschaften, Festschrift zu seinem
60. Geburtstag. Bern, 1949.
316 THE GERMAN
PHASE
technology, on
which science is said to be based.1 It is an even more serious
charge that science is called a degeneration of
"thinking," since it does not really think at all.2
Besides, the "startling" realization is said to emerge
that the sciences cannot comprehend what is meant, for instance,
by nature, by history, and by language. Only reflective meditation
(Besinnung) can do that.3 It is obvious that Heidegger's
increasingly anti-scientific tone is also apt to affect the cause
of any philosophy like phenomenology which aspired to be
scientific, or at least to cooperate with science.
What is the upshot
of Heidegger's long search for Being ?
?. The only
definitive and deliberately simple answer is that Being is
"Itself" (in connection with Being Heidegger often
writes the German pronoun es for Being with a capital E). Most
other statements about it would have to be merely negative.
?. Among the
various characteristics of Being, the outstanding one is its
"truth." Truth, however, is interpreted by ^ >?
Heidegger on the basis of a literal dissection of the Greek word
"a-letheia" as un-hiddenness (Un-verborgenheit) or
openness. Nevertheless, Being is apparently not given oo without
any concealment (B ergon); it also seems to have a tendency to
hide and to withdraw. Its openness is a clearing, but apparently a
clearing in a dark forest, full of Holzwege (blind alleys).
?. The revelation
of Being in its truth is its own doing. It should therefore be
conceived as an active rather than as a passive process, and Being
as in a sense self-determining. Thus Heidegger uses the German
intransitive verb 'ereignen' (to happen) in a new transitive
manner to indicate that Being makes things happen. All that our
thinking can do is to "let Being be" (Seinlassen).
?. Being is
temporal, not timeless or eternal. Although Heidegger has failed
to present the demonstration of this thesis in Sein und Zeit, he
clearly holds to the view that the two are inseparable.
1 Holzwege, p. 267;
Vortrage und. Aufsaze, pp. 45 ff.
3 Was heisst
Denken? p. 4.
3
"Wissenschaft und Besinnung" in Vortrage und Aufsatze,
p. 66.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
317
?. Being has a
history in the sense of a development. This history of Being is
perhaps the main explanation of the seeming inconclusiveness of
Heidegger's search. In reading his Einfuhrung in die Metaphysik
(1935) one receives at first the impression that here at last
Heidegger has found the saving word: namely that Being is presence
(Anwesenheit). However, closer inspection reveals that even this
is at best the answer of the Greeks. It therefore describes merely
the Greek phase in the history of Being, in which only one of its
temporal dimensions had been considered. It has been followed by
other phases, the most fateful one in recent times when Nietzsche
conceived ' of Being as an expression of the will. Thus all the
changing views of Being are actually parts of Being itself. Such
an answer raises, to be sure, the further question as to the
connecting link between all these events in the history of Being:
What is it after all that allows us to ascribe them all to one and
the same substratum. Being?
?. Heidegger's most
recent discussion of Being also suggests that it is the ground of
all things-in-being. Being itself, however, is groundless.1
?. Perhaps the most
significant feature of Being in Heidegger's most recent accounts
of Being is its interdependence with man: Man needs Being, and
Being needs man. Both belong together.2 It hardly needs spelling
out how much such an astonishing estimate can add to the stature
of man at the price of the autonomy of Being. Nevertheless, this
view suggests a final balance between the two poles, Being and
man, the objective and the subjective. To what extent are such
results adequate answers to Heidegger's great initial question,
even in his own sense? At times one might feel that he himself
does not want an answer, but prefers to leave the question open
with all its tantalizing mystery, and that a "genuine
shipwreck" (echtes Scheitern) on the rocks of the question
would satisfy him very well (SZ 148). The last dictum of Was
heisst Denken?, especially in the form of the lecture as published
separately in Vortrage und Aufsatze, seems to imply
1 Der Satz vom
Grund, p. 205.
2 Der Satz von der
Identitat, p. 22 ff.
THE GERMAN PHASE
318
that we are not
even yet ready to receive an answer. We are at best on our way, in
the "neighborhood" of Being. Now it may well be that we
are not yet ready. But how about Heidegger himself? How can he
tell us that we are close to the answer unless he himself knows it
? Thus far he has not revealed to us that he does, and the only
chance is that it is to be found in his desk, in that section of
Sein und Zeit which he is no longer willing to release.
5. Heidegger's
Conception of Phenomenology
Thus far we have
studied merely the role of phenomenology in the history of
Heidegger's thinking without trying to give a full idea of what he
means by it. It is now time to fill this gap. We shall do so by
first taking account of Heidegger's own interpretation of
phenomenology and then by observing it in action in some of its
more instructive applications.
There would seem to
be little point in discussing Heidegger's conception of
phenomenology prior to Sein und Zeit. For the references to
phenomenology in the Duns Scotus book suggest that at that period
Heidegger believed himself to be in complete agreement with
Husserl's interpretation of it. By contrast, Sein und Zeit reveals
that Heidegger had gone considerably beyond Husserl, and that he
was fully aware of it. We shall therefore begin with an analysis
of the phenomenology of Sein und Zeit. Subsequently we shall
discuss Heidegger's later methodology, with a view to determining
how far this can still be considered as phenomenological.
a. hermeneutic
phenomenology - Heidegger introduces his own conception of
phenomenology in the second (methodological) chapter of the
introduction to Sein und Zezt, after having stated in a first
chapter "necessity, structure, and prerogative of the
question of Being." But before characterizing this
phenomenology itself, he discusses a task whose solution he
considers indispensable before the question of Being can be
attacked with any chance of success: the so-called destruction,
also named the "phenomenological destruction," of
ontology.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
319
The need of such a
purge is a consequence of Heidegger's conviction that no fresh
start can be made until we have identified and neutralized the
metaphysical preconceptions which falsify the very formulations of
our philosophical problems, in fact even the description of our
phenomena. Words such as "consciousness,"
"subject," or "substance" are the results of
metaphysical theories which have vitiated our whole approach to
the phenomena. In this respect even Husserl's phenomenology is
still too naively dependent on tradition and anything but free
from presuppositions. It is the task of phenomenological
destruction to liberate us from unconscious servitude to our
metaphysical past.
However, the
iconoclastic term "destruction" is not to be understood
in the merely negative sense of a repudiation of all tradition or
of any kind of ontological nihilism or relativism. Instead,
"destruction" is characterized as a loosening up of the
hardened tradition and the removal (Ablosung) of the screens
(Verdeckungen) for which tradition is responsible. Destruction in
this sense has actually a positive referent, the primordial
(ursprungliche) experiences from which the tradition was formed,
and which constitute its birth certificates. It is in this sense
that Heidegger intends to "destroy" the history of
ontology at the three decisive crossroads of western philosophy,
Kant, Descartes, and Aristotle (in that order), in an obvious
attempt to retrace and reverse the steps these thinkers had taken.
It is, however significant that in the outline of Sein und Zeit
Heidegger postponed this destruction to the second half of the
work, which ha? shared the fate of Part I, Section 3. Apparently
it was thus not phenomenology which presupposed the destruction,
but destruction which presupposed the phenomenology of the
original experiences.
What, then, is
phenomenology in Heidegger's sense? In the published parts of Sein
und Zeit Heidegger offers two conceptions of phenomenology, the
more developed one actually only of a preliminary nature
(Vorbegriff), the definitive one, called the idea (Idee) of
phenomenology, unfortunately sketched only in a passing manner
which appears to be a prelude for a fuller treatment, presumably
in the missing parts of Sein und Zeit. Thus the preliminary
concept still is, to all intents and purposes, Heideg-
320 THE GERMAN
PHASE
ger's most explicit
formulation of his own conception of phenomenology.1
From the very start
Heidegger made it amply clear that what he understands by
phenomenology in Sein und Zeit was not identical with what Husserl
meant by it, and that he claimed the right to develop it on his
own beyond the stage it had reached with Husserl. To be sure, he
saw in Husserl's phenomenology the indispensable foundation for
such a development, but significantly enough, in this context he
mentioned only the"break-through" to phenomenology in
the Logische Untersuchungen, not the Ideen, its developed form.
Even more significant, he states that it is not the essential
thing about phenomenology to be actual as a philosophical school
("Richtung"): "Potentiality stands higher than
actuality. To understand phenomenology consists in seizing it as a
potentiality." (p. 38) Also, to Heidegger phenomenology is
neither a "standpoint" nor a "school":
it cannot ever
become one "as long as it understands itself." For:
The term
"phenomenology" means primarily a concept of method. It
does not characterize the qualitative content (das sachhaltige
Was) of the objects of philosophical research, but the mode of
approaching them (das Wie). . . . The title
"phenomenology" expresses a maxim which can be
formulated thus: "To the things themselves!" - in
contrast to all the unsupported (freischwebenden) constructions,
the accidental findings, the blind acceptance of concepts verified
merely in appearance, and the pseudo-questions which, often for
generations, strut about (sich breit-machen) as
"problems." One might reply, however, that this maxim is
after all pretty obvious (reichlich selbstverstandlich) and,
besides, an expression of the principles of all scientific
knowledge. One does not understand why this triviality should be
included explicitly under the head (Titelbezeichnung) of a type of
research. It is indeed a 'triviality' (Selbsiverstdndlichkeit)
which is at stake, one which we want to approach more closely
insofar as this is relevant to the elucidation of the method of
this treatise (p. 27 f.)
Heidegger's
preliminary account of this seemingly "trivial" method
takes its characteristic point of departure from an analysis of
the word "phenomenology" in which the two components
"phenomenon" and "logos" are distinguished and
inter-
1 The one contained
in his counter-draft to Husserl's Encyclopaedia Britannica article
(see p. 280) was hardly meant to be much more than an attempt to
help Husserl in the formulation of his own conception, in a manner
that seemed to Heidegger more effective; witness the occurrence of
the term "consciousness" in this definition, a terra
which Heidegger had already eliminated at the stage of Sein und
Zeit.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
321
preted first
separately. The result differs from Husserl's interpretation so
vastly that it might be well to start here by contrasting the two.
When Husserl took
up the term "phenomenology," as shown in Ch. Ill (p.
103) he gave no explicit definition or discussion of what he meant
by "phenomenon." It was only as his idea of
phenomenology crystallized into something distinctive and
fundamental for philosophy that he felt the need for a
redefinition. After abandoning Brentano's sense of the term in
Logische Untersuchungen (II, 1, p. 371), he assigned to it a
precise meaning, first in his momentous lectures on the "Idea
of Phenomenology" of 1907, and then in the Introduction to
the Ideen. Here the "pure phenomena" of the new
phenomenology are described as non-individual, i.e., as the
general essences of empirical phenomena obtained by the eidetic
reduction, and, in addition to that, as non-real, refined by the
phenomenological reduction, which had bracketed their reality.
Consequently, their ontological or metaphysical status was
deliberately left undecided at the start, while the final word was
that they owed their being to consciousness.
No such neutrality,
let alone dependence upon consciousness, is implied in Heidegger's
concept of phenomenon. Instead, "phenomenon" is here
interpreted as "what shows itself," more specifically
even as "what shows itself in person (das
Sich-an-ihm-selbst-zeigende) or what is manifest (das
Offenbare)." This manifestness does not preclude the
possibility that at times Heidegger's phenomenon hides behind a
misleading appearance. But it is clear that it is not the
distillate of special reductive operations. It is rather an
autonomous entity with powers of its own, independent of and prior
to our thinking.
However, this does
not mean that Heidegger simply returned to the colloquial use of
the word "phenomenon" as used in ordinary discourse and
also in science. True, Heidegger took cognizance of the common
(vulgar} sense of the word as one among several others, notably
one which applies to the empirical world, and which is presumably
also the "phenomenon" of natural science. From this
Heidegger distinguished the "phenomenological concept of
phenomenon" as that of a phenomenon which "first and
foremost" (zunachst und zumeist) does not show
THE GERMAN PHASE
322
itself but remains
hidden as the meaning (Sinn) and ground {Grund) of what shows
itself (p. 35).
Hence the
"phenomenological phenomenon" requires much more by way
of direct demonstration and verification than a merely descriptive
phenomenology, which Heidegger mentions only in passing, and for
which he seems to have little use. It calls for a method which
makes us see what is normally hidden and forgotten. Now
"logos," the second component of the word
"phenomenology," means in Heidegger's intensifying
interpretation of its literal meaning a method of making us see
what is otherwise concealed, of taking the hidden out of its
hiding, and of detecting it as "unhidden," i.e., as
truth {a-letheia) l Thus phenomenology in the genuine sense of the
word becomes to Heidegger the method of uncovering the hiding or
"interpretation" (Auslegung), which he also calls the
methodical meaning of phenomenological description, (p. 37).
Now the primary
phenomenon which needs uncovering in this sense is Being, the
victim of our usual forgetfulness of the "ontological
difference" between Being and the things-in-being. In fact,
for Heidegger the science of Being of the things-in-being or
ontology is declared possible only as phenomenology. Moreover,
although no further reason is given, it turns out that for
Heidegger even the converse holds: according to its content
phenomenology coincides with ontology. Having gone so far,
Heidegger finally concludes that philosophy itself is nothing but
"universal phenomenological ontology based on the
hermeneutics of human being (Dasein)," which by implication
makes phenomenology the one and only philosophical method.
Quite apart from
the startling boldness of this deduction, the idea of such a
phenomenological ontology contrasts sharply with Husserl's
conception. For to Husserl, at least at that time, the name
"ontology" stood not for the science of the Being of
things-in-being, but primarily for a branch of his pure logic,
i.e., the eidetic science of the pervasive categories of all
things-in-
1 He is, however,
not the first to suggest this. See Nicolai Hartmann, Platos Logik
des Seins (Marburg, 1909), p. 477. - As to the philological
soundness of this interpretation see now Paul Friedlander, Plato
I, Ch. XI: Aletheia. For Heidegger's etymology and etymologizing
philosophy of logos see also Was heisst Denken ? pp. 120 ff., 170
ff. and Vortrdge und Aufsatze, pp. 257 ff. Husserl's meaning of
"logos" as developed in Formate und transzendentale
Logik deals only with the several strata of logical entities.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
323
being (formal
ontology), followed by "regional" ontologies dealing
with the supreme categories of each science in their different
essential natures. True, in Husserl's conception even these
ontologies had to be underpinned by phenomenological derivation
from original intuitions. But such a phenomenologic-ally supported
ontology was clearly restricted to a limited area of the
things-in-being rather than to Being as such. Heidegger's is
restricted in a very different sense, inasmuch as it deals only
with a certain feature of all things-in-being. Presumably he would
leave Husserl's problems completely to the sciences.
But what exactly is
the new type of interpretation which Heidegger's phenomenological
ontology demands? It is in this connection that the term
"hermeneutics" appears in Heidegger's phenomenology,
which also goes by the name of "hermeneutic
phenomenology." Hermeneutics is not a new term. It has its
origin in Biblical exegesis and has also been applied to the
interpretation of historical documents; Dilthey, to whom Heidegger
pays repeated tribute, brought the word into prominence. But as
Heidegger now uses the term it no longer refers to documents or
symbolic expressions, but to non-symbolic facts of the real world,
to human being or Dasein. In fact it is the interpretation of this
particular type of being for which Heidegger reserves the term
"hermeneutic." Only indirectly is hermeneutics relevant
to ontology in general, since it deals with Dasein, i.e., that
type of being which provides the foundation for the interpretation
of Being in general (p. 47).
What does it mean
to "interpret" such a non-symbolic fact as human being?
Interpretation aims at the meaning of the thing interpreted. It
therefore presupposes that what is to be interpreted has meaning.
Now it is one of Heidegger's basic assertions that human being has
meaning in a sense which admits of interpretation. For human being
is essentially related to its own being as that which is "at
stake" for it: "The essence of being consists in its
being toward" (Zu-sein) (p. 42). That "toward
which" human being exists consists, to be sure, primarily in
a possibility, notably the possibility of being authentic or
inauthentic. Hence in this orientation toward possibilities beyond
itself, human being is capable of an interpretation which
identifies these
THE GERMAN PHASE
324
possibilities ahead
of itself by determining its "what-for" (woraufhin,
um-zu}.
But human being is
not only capable of such interpretation, it also demands it. For
just as Being has a tendency to fall into oblivion, so human Being
has an inherent tendency to degenerate. Heidegger calls this in
German Verfallen, which may be understood in the sense of decay
but also of infatuation and escape, a characteristic of the
everyday mode of human being from which hermeneutic phenomenology
has to take its start. This also explains why hermeneutic
interpretation has to swim, as it were, against the current, and
to use a certain violence, as Heidegger candidly admits.
This poses the
problem of how such an interpretation can actually be carried out
and what its criteria are. Heidegger himself points out that
understanding and interpretation depend on certain preconceptions.
Thus every interpretation of ordinary items in daily life is
related to a frame of relevance (Bewandtnis-ganzheit) which
embraces it (Vorhabe), implies a preview (Vor-sicht) looking
toward anticipated meanings, and requires conceptual patterns for
it [Vorgriff) (p. 150). Heidegger admits that this procedure is
anything but free from presuppositions, and that it has all the
earmarks of a vicious circle. He maintains, however, that the
anticipations of hermeneutic interpretation are not determined by
chance ideas or popular conceptions but by the "things
themselves." He makes no attempt to link this procedure with
general scientific methods other than those used in the historical
studies. But it would not seem too difficult to relate it to the
logic of hypothesis, if not to the use of heuristic concepts.
Hermeneutic
phenomenology may thus be defined as a method of bringing out the
normally hidden purposes of such goal-determined things-in-being
as human beings. It presupposes, of course, that these beings
possess such a purposeful structure;
but there seems to
be no reason why this presupposition should not be verifiable and
also actually verified. Hermeneutics thus uses methods which go
beyond mere description of what is manifest and tries to uncover
hidden meanings by anticipatory devices. It is almost surprising
that they are not compared and contrasted with the techniques of
psychoanalysis in its attempts
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
325
to uncover the
unconscious. One can only suspect that for Heidegger these would
be of much too conceptual or theoretical a nature, and lacking in
a sufficiently basic interpretation ot human being within the
total frame of Being.
To be sure, all
this still concerns only the preliminary concept of Heidegger's
phenomenology. It leaves the question of its definitive concept
unanswered. As to this, the only clues which Heidegger supplies in
Sein und Zeit occur in a section close to the end of the
existential analysis of human being (p. 357 ff.). Here, after
temporality has been diagnosed as the final "sense of the
Being of human being," Heidegger tries to apply this new
insight to various human enterprises, among them science. And
since, especially at this stage, Heidegger still considers
phenomenology a science, this interpretation has bearing on
phenomenology as well. Science, or more specifically theoretical
scientific activity, is here interpreted as a modification of our
usual circumspect concern with our environment. In this activity
our practical interests are either neutralized or overlooked.
However, no application of this general interpretation of science
to the science of phenomenology is given. It stands to reason that
it would show even the phenomenological approach as a restriction
of the concrete meaning of everyday living. On the other hand
phenomenology might be at the same time the very kind of
scientific interpretation which could reveal the limitations of
the merely scientific approach.
In what sense and
to what extent, then, can hermeneutic phenomenology claim to be
phenomenology in the original sense of the term? Quite apart from
the element of violence needed in the kind of interpretation
Heidegger performs, it certainly goes beyond the
"immediately" given, if immediacy means manifest
givenness. It requires anticipations which go beyond it, as any
explanatory hypothesis does, and requires extrapolation beyond
what is directly present. Certainly this is phenomenology in an
enlarged sense. Whether in spite of this it should be acknowledged
as genuine phenomenology must largely depend on how far it is
possible to underpin its extrapolations to the meanings of the
phenomena by intuitive verification of a more than merely private
and persuasive nature. To what extent has Heidegger succeeded in
doing this?
326
THE GERMAN PHASE
b. Hermeneutics in
action - This section will attempt to present some representative
examples of hermeneutic phenomenology, concentrating on those
which have achieved a certain notoriety. Without question
Heidegger's most substantial phe-nomenological analyses occur in
Sein und Zeit. No attempt will be made to render the argument of
this work, although we shall follow its sequence of topics. It
will, however, be well to recall Heidegger's methodological
strategy. He starts with a "preparatory analysis of human
being," which takes its departure from what is given
"first and foremost" (zundchst und zumeist) in our
everyday existence (Alltaglichkeif). It is only on this foundation
that he advances to a level of interpretation which digs down to
the deeper origins of meaning (ursprungliche existentiale
Interpretation).
The main difficulty
in the presentation of the following examples is due to the
extreme condensation of Heidegger's accounts. Rarely, if ever,
does he give descriptions in the sense of the earlier
phenomenologists. He mostly points at the phenomena by means of
new, provocative and, at times, stunning terms which keep even the
native German groping his way toward a tentative understanding.
(I) Ipseity
('Jemeinigkeit') and 'Existence.' Heidegger begins his analysis
with the provocative sentence:
"The
thing-in-being whose analysis is our task is we ourselves. The
being of this thing-in-being is each one's "mine" (je
meines)." (p. 41). To this personalized character of being
Heidegger then attaches the synthetic label J emeinigkeit, which,
translated literally, would amount to something like
"each-his-ownness." "Ipseity" has at least
dictionary status and might do for our purposes. What does it
involve?
Heidegger's
conception is clearly related to Kierkegaard's picture of the
single existing individual in his ultimate loneliness, although
Heidegger does not mention him in this context. However Heidegger
is not interested in this aspect for its own sake, but for the
sake of ontology. His main point is the fact that human being in
its "ipseity" is "related to" (verhalt sich
zu) man's own personal being, to which it is "handed
over" (uberantwortef). This is interpreted immediately in the
sense that human being
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
327
is directed toward
this, its own being (Zu-sein) and that it is this being which is
at stake for it in its living - in fact that such being is its
only stake. (This interpretation is as essential to Heideggers'
ultimate objective as it may seem questionable to a more sceptical
reader. For even if ipseity should prove to be one of the
fundamental characteristics of human being, does it follow that
essentially it is preoccupied by the question of Being, and
primarily of its own being?)
From ipseity with
its concern for one's own being Heidegger also derives the insight
that human being is always oriented toward future possibilities of
its own. For the fundamental possibility of choosing these
possibilities, especially the possibilities which he calls
"to be oneself or not to be oneself," i.e., to assume
one's authentic way of being or to dodge it, Heidegger introduces
the term "existence," in a sense which clearly differs
from all previous usages. Scholastic as well as Kierkegaardian. It
is in this sense that we are to understand Heidegger's key
sentence: "The essence (Wesen) of human being lies in its
existence," i.e., in its possibilities to choose different
ways of being. One might well wonder whether this is not an
overstatement, since even possibility presupposes at least some
actualization as its base. In fact, later characterizations make
it clear that "existence" in this narrowest sense does
not exhaust the "essence" of human being but that it
also includes such actualized characteristics as facticity
(Geworfenheit) and falling-for (Verfallen), about which we shall
hear more.
In considering
Heidegger's concept of "existence" one must not overlook
the fact that after Sein und Zeit he introduces one more sense of
the term, namely as man's "standing in the clearing of being,
"as "being open for the openness of being," or as
"standing in the midst of being" in such a way that he
has access to being.1 Heidegger's new spelling of the term,
"Ek-sistenz" in his later writings, which first appears
in Vom Wesen der Wahrheit (1943), is a typical attempt to
resurrect the etymological literal sense of a
1 To be sure,
Heidegger does not seem to admit that there has been such a shift.
Thus in the Nachwort to Was ist Metaphysik? (Sixth Edition, 1951,
p. 14) he maintains that even in Sein und Zeit existence meant the
"openness of the human being, who stands open for the
openness of being" and that he "stands in this openness
by enduring it" (ausstehen). A similar unacknowledged
reinterpretation takes place in the case of concern (Sorge), which
is no longer confined to human being, but referred to being as
such.
328 THE GERMAN
PHASE
word. Even more
startling is the characterization of human being as
"ec-static," i.e., as "standing in the clearing of
being"; in fact now man himself is called the "clearing
of being."1 No derivation, phenomenological or otherwise, of
this transition from the first to the second interpretation is
given. It reflects the change from the hermeneutics of human being
to the "thought" of Being.
(2) Being-in-the
World. Possibly the most important structural characteristic
considered in hermeneutic phenomenology is being-in-the-world
(in-der-Welt-sein). For human being, as Heidegger understands it,
does not, and even cannot, occur except in the framework of an
encompassing world with which it belongs together, into which it
-finds itself inserted. This is not simply a matter of a
part-whole relationship, where the human being is encased in the
world like a box within a box. The relationship is much more
intimate. Both are what they are only in being related to one
another.
If thus
being-in-the-world is the basic structure of human being,
consciousness and particularly knowledge are only modifications of
this underlying fundamental relationship. However, within this
close-knit relationship Heidegger distinguishes three components:
(1) world, (2) that which is in the world, (3) the relation of
being "in." They are analyzed at first separately.
Under the heading
of "worldliness" (W eitlichkeit) of the world Heidegger
investigates the world of daily experience in contrast to the
derivative world of science. It has its center in human being and
coincides with our subjective environment (Umwelt) or milieu
insofar as it is experienced. Heidegger shows impressively how the
things within this world are given primarily not as physical
objects, which simply occur "before our hands"
(vor-handen), but as usable things or utensils (Zeug), which refer
to possible applications within a practical world and are thus
"handy" (zuhanden). Things of this type refer to one
another and form systems of mutual reference of meaning.
While not entirely
novel, these analyses represent perhaps one of the most
interesting and fruitful parts of hermeneutic phenomenology. They
have influenced particularly the attempts of phenomenological
psychopathologists such as Ludwig Bins-
1 "Brief uber
den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit, p. 69.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
329
wanger to
understand the world of psychopathic personalities in its inner
coherence. World and worldliness embrace and support the otherwise
unrelated intentional structures distinguished by early Husserlian
phenomenology. Yet it must not be overlooked that Heidegger's own
interest in these structures is only transitional, since he uses
human being only as his point of departure for the analysis of its
Being, not as its destination.
(3) The Impersonal
('People'). An even more influential example of hermeneutic
phenomenology occurs in connection with the analysis of the
carrier, the "who," of human existence in the world. It
begins with an important discussion of the ego - an unreliable
guide for hermeneutics - and of social existence in a shared
world. After that, in less than four pages, Heidegger gives one of
the most impressive accounts of everyday personal existence in its
tendency to escape from itself and to fall into inauthentic being
(Verfallen). As such it accepts the guidance and control of the
subject signified by the impersonal pronoun "one" or
"people" (the German "man"). Thus
"one" is constantly concerned about keeping at the
proper distance from other people, yet at the same time in a state
of subservience which allows the other to determine the form of
his existence. "One" wants to keep close to the average.
Other possibilities of existence are levelled down by our constant
regard for what "people" do. Thus the "one"
takes over the load of our personal existence, makes us exist in a
dependent and inauthentic fashion. Human existence is first and
foremost that of "one," not of "self."
There are, to be
sure, plenty of precedents and successors for this interpretation
among writers both philosophical and non-philosophical.
Sociologists will inevitably be reminded of G. H. Mead's concept
of the "generalized other." But quite apart from the
problem of the exact meaning of his conception, its general
framework is quite different. And so is its evaluation:
Mead is concerned
with the evolutionary problem of the social matrix from which the
individual self arises. For Heidegger it is a matter of describing
a form of inauthentic social existence in which the individual
tries to escape into an impersonalized average existence. The
problem of authentic existence hardly seems to arise for Mead. -
David Riesmann's concept of other-
THE GERMAN PHASE
330
directedness would
be a more pertinent recent equivalent of Heidegger's
"people."
"Naked is he
(the concrete man) flung into the world .." William James in
The Sentiment of Rationality
(4) Moods and
'Facticity.' Before Heidegger, moods (in German
"Stimmungen," i.e., literally "attunements")
may have been of some interest to psychologists and
phenomenologists of feeling. But in contrast to the
"intentional" or referential feelings, moods were
usually considered as merely subjective affairs, of no cognitive
significance beyond their own whimsical occurrence. This changes
in the light of Heidegger's hermeneutics. Now that human being has
been found to be inserted into a world with meanings centered in
it, and now that the center of this world has been considered, the
question of their relation is raised, i.e., that of man's
existence within such a world. For this relation Heidegger uses
the equivalent of the English 'being there,' i.e. Da-sein, this
time spelled with the two components of the word separated and
hyphenated in the obvious intention of reviving their literal
meanings. For we are there in this world in the sense of finding
ourselves in a peculiar fundamental situation [Befindlichkeit). It
is Heidegger's contention that we can find out about the meaning
of this fundamental situation by interpreting certain fundamental
moods. Strangely enough, the moods which he selects are not so
much those where we are "in tune," but those that show
us out of tune (or "sorts,") such as fear and anxiety.
What they reveal is Being as a burden. Even the elated moods
reveal this by way of liberating us from this burden (p. 134).
(Why this interpretation is the correct one, and not rather its
opposite, is never discussed. There is, after all, the buoyancy of
those who seem to be supported by the surge of something like a
vital elan, whose absence is revealed in the depressive moods).
The burden of human
existence as thus manifested according to Heidegger consists in
the poignant fact that human being "is and has to be,"
"whence and whither, however, remain in the dark." This
is obviously the feeling expressed in the well-known lines of
Edward Fitzgerald's Omar Khayyam'.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
331
I came like water,
and like wind I go Into this Universe, and Why not knowing Nor
Whence, like water willy-nilly flowing.
For this situation
of facticity Heidegger coins the striking though ponderous word
"Geworfenheit," which would have to be rendered by a
passive participle of verbs like to throw, to fling, or to cast.
However, to Heidegger "thrownness" is not a mere brute
fact:
it represents an
intimate part of our way of being, even though it is usually
pushed into the background. Moods also give access to certain
characters of our world as a whole, of our social being, and of
our existential possibilities. Thus threateningness or
dreadfulness is revealed to us in the mood of fear or dread.
In none of these
interpretations does Heidegger ever raise the question whether and
to what extent moods are reliable guides for an understanding of
the world, even if they should be good clues for the
interpretation of our own feeling about it. This question is all
the more urgent since some moods are taken as signs of the
opposite of what they seem to attest. No matter how significant
one considers these interpretations, the question of their
limitations is inescapable.1
(5) Anxiety and
Nothingness. Few items in Heidegger's philosophy have given rise
to more protests and even ridicule than these. Anxiety (Angst), as
Heidegger sees it, is the most revealing of all the fundamental
situations (Grundbefindlichkeiten). But what does it reveal? In
order to appraise this, one must consider Heidegger's distinction
between anxiety and fear in their hermeneutic significance.
Fear is
characterized as a mode of human being in which we are afraid of
something more or less definite, notably the dreadful. Its stake
(worum) is human being itself. The function of fear is to expose
us to the threatening in a way which makes us concerned. This
characterization by function, in which the directional aspects,
the source, and the stake of the experience are stressed, whereas
its intrinsic nature is not even mentioned, constitutes a good
illustration of the difference between hermeneutic and descriptive
phenomenology.
1 0. F. Bollnow in
his book Das Wesen der Stimmungen (Frankfurt, Vittorio
Klostermann, 1942) gives an important critical development of
Heidegger's analyses with very different results.
332 THE GERMAN
PHASE
By contrast,
anxiety is described as the condition which is behind our everyday
escape into (small) talk, curiosity, and ambiguity. What threatens
us here and makes us flee is "nothing in particular,"
something which is "nothing and nowhere." Ultimately
Heidegger diagnoses the object of anxiety as the world as such and
our whole position in this world. In such a state of anxiety the
world appears with the peculiar character of un-canniness
(Unheimlichkeif). The "nothing" revealed by the anxiety
of Sein und Zeit thus consists of the uncanny indefiniteness of
the world as a whole and of our being in the world.
The interpretation
of anxiety and of the nothing to which it refers is pushed
somewhat further in the lecture Was ist Metaphysik?, which has
attracted particular attention. Here the "nothing"
serves as a direct foil for Being itself, Heidegger's real concern
in his seeming preoccupation with nothingness. Anxiety is now
interpreted as a pulling away from the nothing. He identifies this
nothing with the things-in-being in their entirety. In this
experience they seem to drop away from us and to hold us off at
the same time. It could perhaps be compared with the experience of
agoraphobia, in which the more distant objects seem to recede from
us, or with the pattern of the expanding universe according to the
latest astronomic views. It is this peculiar movement which to
Heidegger makes the essence of what is commonly called
"nothing." Hence Heidegger's nothing is not an entity
but an event or character which attaches to the world in the
peculiar mood of anxiety. For this event Heidegger coins a special
verb from the noun nothing, "nichten." It is therefore
unfair to charge Heidegger with having hypostatized the nothing,
while it is true that he denies the origin of the term from
negation or from a process like annihilation. Against the
background of this experience Being stands out all the more
clearly and poignantly. It is another question how far the
character of nothingness is the necessary obverse of the
experience of Being, as Heidegger implies.
Even more startling
and provocative is Heidegger's formula for man's position in
relation to this "nothing": "Human being is
suspension (Hineingehaltenheit) into the nothing"; or
"man is the stand-in (Platzhalter) for the nothing." The
second, quaintly striking formulation seems to suggest that the
nothing is a
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
333
phenomenon which
depends on human beings and could not be without them. The first,
even more daring, assigns to the nothing the status of a
surrounding medium. Both convey the idea of a unique distinction
of man as a being who stands not only in the midst of being, but
also finds himself exposed to the possibility of non-being, and
who in this sense can transcend the mere fact of his being.
(6) Concern
('Serge') as the Fundamental Structure of Human Being. Thus far
the hermeneutics of being-in-the-world with its various
expressions has not yet supplied the pervading clue by which
Heidegger would like to make human existence intelligible, and
which he calls the Being of human being. It is the function of the
phenomenology of anxiety as the fundamental mood of the human
situation to bring out this structure. Anxiety is always concerned
about the existential possibilities of human being, caught by its
facticity and trying to escape into everyday existence. Human
being thus shows a threefold directedness:
(1) it is ahead of
itself toward its future possibilities (Sich-vorweg-sein); (2) it
is already involved in its factual being (schon-sein in ...); (3)
it is lost in the world of its daily occupations (sein bei ...).
For this threefold structure Heidegger uses the German word Sorge.
It can best be rendered by the much more appropriate
"concern," "care" being a more dubious
equivalent, since Heidegger, none too successfully, wants to
exclude all connotations of worry. Concern, then, is at the root
of all our dealings, especially our practical dealings and
aspirations in our everyday life, our willing and wishing. It
shows man as primarily reaching out into the future, as tied to
his past into which he finds himself "thrown," and as
diverted by the world of his present.
"On the
dialectical or ideal (not biological) relation of life to death I
think Heidegger is splendid."
George Santayana,
Letters, p. 381.
(7) Death. All the
preceding analyses are included by Heidegger among the preparatory
ones. One of the most characteristic examples of existential
interpretation on the deeper level (ursprunglich) is that of
death. Compared, for instance, with
334 THE GERMAN
PHASE
Scheler's
posthumously published analysis of death1 it might seem rather
meager. Thus Heidegger never attempts to describe the way in which
the process of dying constitutes itself, however inadequately and
distantly, in human consciousness. Yet, what Heidegger is
interested in is not the phenomenon of death, but its role as the
event which "completes" human existence. Thus he
identifies and characterizes death only as the most authentic
possibility of human existence, the one in which existence itself
becomes impossible. Human existence is essentially "existence
toward death." This does not mean that death is the goal of
human existence. But it does mean that it is oriented toward it,
at least by way of anticipation.
Much about
Heidegger's interpretation of man's attitude toward death as the
ultimate possibility which ends all possibility, and about his
attempts to escape it is impressive. Nevertheless, one wonders why
facing this possibility in stern resoluteness should be his one
and only authentic possibility. True, Heidegger is not obsessed by
the physical or theological aspects of death. Nevertheless, he
does not even consider any alternative authentic possibilities of
human existence, such as the fulfillment of a life project in the
spirit of Goethe's Faust or the supreme unconcern about death of
Spinoza's wise man.
The same pattern
can be observed in Heidegger's hermeneutics of conscience, of
guilt, and of resoluteness (Entschlossenheit), a word which in its
German literalized meaning expresses to Heidegger a certain type
of openness (Erschlossenheit). A somber preoccupation with
necessary failure, with guilt and futility (Nichtigkeit) seems to
permeate this whole section of Sein und Zeit more than any other
part of the book. However, Heidegger always refuses to put these
interpretations into a theological framework. This very fact may
have made them all the more attractive to theologians, who could
look upon them as independent confirmations of their revelational
diagnoses of the human condition.
(8) Temporality.
With the subject of temporality we reach the point or
"horizon" from where Heidegger hopes to answer not only
the question of the meaning of human being but of Being
"Tod und
Fortleben" in Nachlass I. p. 1-52; Gesammelte Werke X, 9-64.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
335
itself. The
published parts of Sein und Zeit lead at least far enough to show
how time is rooted in human existence in the form of
"temporality."
Temporality is
introduced as the "meaning" of the concern (Sorge) which
makes up the Being of human being. It is not exactly easy to
determine what "meaning" signifies in this context.
Indications are that what Heidegger has in mind is something like
a frame of reference or "horizon" for the projects of
human existence; but there also seems to be the connotation of a
final purpose (woraufhin), which makes our secondary projects
possible (p. 324). However, there is a clear parallelism between
temporality in its three phases of future, present, and past, and
the three aspects of Sorge in which we are ahead of ourselves
toward the possibilities of future existence, are immersed in the
facticity of our past, and "fall for" the escapes of our
present.
In the pattern of
temporality Heidegger assigns priority to the future, which he
interprets, in accordance with one literal meaning of the German
word "Zukunft," as that which comes toward us. This
future is even said to originate our present and our past. Another
feature that goes with this is that temporality is not properly a
thing-in-being. It is not even correct to say that time
"has" being. Rather does it "temporalize"
itself. The German word which Heidegger uses in this context,
"zeitigen," is not completely new. In ordinary contexts
it stands either reflexively for the coming into being (sich
zeitigen) or transitively for the bringing into being of various
things as time goes on. But one could certainly not say that time
itself is the result of Zeitigung.1 While Heidegger does not give
any definition of the term, one gathers that time has a mode of
being completely its own. It almost sounds as if time produced
itself like a causa sui, since it does not seem to originate from
human beings or from Being in general.
Temporality is also
characterized as "ecstatic." There are no signs that
Heidegger wants this term to be understood in the
1 As mentioned
before (p. 149) the term appears also in an extended sense, in the
manuscripts, mostly unpublished, of Husserl's later period, which
deal with the deepest layer of constitution in consciousness, the
constitution of time. Whether the term drifted from Heidegger to
Husserl must remain an open question. Certainly, if so, it has
changed its meaning in the process.
336 THE GERMAN
PHASE
traditional sense
of a mystic ecstasy. Rather does he think of an intensified
literal meaning of the word, in the sense of standing beside
itself (ausser sich), which is used to convey the idea that human
being in its temporality is always reaching out beyond itself,
that it is beyond itself, i.e., in the future which "comes
toward" it, that it goes back to its past facticity, and that
it meets its present. Thus future, past, and present are also
called the "ecstasies" of temporality (p. 329).
Temporality, at least in the form in which it is the backbone of
human being, does not consist of unrelated phases, but forms a
dynamic system of references in which one form implies the other.
There is of course
still a considerable gap between the mere temporality of human
being and the time of Being in general. But it stands to reason
that what Heidegger has in mind is a certain parallelism between
the time structures on both levels. In view of the incompleteness
of Heidegger's philosophy of time it would be hard to evaluate it
as to its originality and its adequacy. According to his own
testimony, it has grown chiefly out of his dialogue (Gesprach)
with Aristotle, Augustine, Kant, and Hegel. However, he rejects
Bergson's ideas with almost surprising violence. Perhaps the most
original feature of Heidegger's conception is the emphasis on the
prerogative of the future. To be sure, certain ideas of Whitehead,
of John Dewey, and of G. H. Mead could be related to it without
too much effort. Heidegger's interpretation, however, differs very
significantly from Husserl's descriptive phenomenology of our
inner time consciousness as contained in his Gottingen lectures of
1905, which Heidegger edited and published one year after the
appearance of Sein und Zeit.
To what extent can
temporality be accepted as the sense of human existence in any
ordinary meaning of the word "sense" ? It would hardly
do to say that the passage of temporality and time makes up the
sense of human being. At best one might understand it as the
setting or raw material of our being. It is hard to shake off the
impression that in these sections Heidegger is so preoccupied with
the more general ontological problem that he no longer cares for
an intelligible interpretation of human life rather than for what
function temporality may have as a clue to the structure of Being
as such.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
337
(p) Historicity.
Before Heidegger, phenomenologists had attached only limited and
secondary importance to the problem of history. Husserl had even
launched a vigorous attack on historicism as one of the many forms
of contemporary relativism. This, however, did not mean that he
wanted to ignore history completely. Thus the phenomenological
"platform" of 1913 had expressed the idea that
phenomenology would be in a position to utilize the insights of
the earlier philosophy much more fully than ever before. Husserl
himself, in his selective way, had tried increasingly to relate
his enterprise to the previous history of thought and to justify
it in this light.
From the very start
Heidegger's attitude toward history was of a very different
nature. Historical studies were one of his first major interests.
As a Catholic theologian he had immersed himself not only in
Thomism but also in its sources in Aristotle, in Augustine, and in
the mystic tradition of Master Eckhart. In the philosophical
atmosphere around Heinrich Rickert he had then developed an
intense interest in German idealist thought from Kant to Hegel and
particularly in Nietzsche. But he had also become deeply
interested in the problems of history as such, of historiography,
and of its theory, particularly along the lines of Wilhelm
Dilthey. Later on, especially during his Marburg years, his
interest spread backwards to Plato and to the very beginnings of
Greek thought in the Pre-Socratics (a term which Heidegger
detests). If there is any area which he has comparatively
neglected, it is that of Anglo-American philosophy.
As early as his
inaugural lecture of 1915, Heidegger had taken up the problem of
historical time as distinguished from the time of the physical
sciences. It now found its proper place in the existential
analysis of human being. Later developments have made it clear
that he assigns to history a major place in the structure not only
of the things-in-being but also of Being itself. We noted before
that his strongest objection to Husserl has been the latter's lack
of a sense of history.
It would be
misleading, however, to see in Heidegger's interest in history
simply an increased accent on historical studies within
phenomenology. Actually the very translation of Heidegger's
vocabulary involves a problem for the proper understanding of his
real concern. German has at least two terms for history,
338 THE GERMAN
PHASE
"Geschichte"
and "Historic." Since the latter is somewhat
old-fashioned and obsolete, Heidegger reserves it for the merely
antiquarian study of the past, in which he does not want to have
any part. "Geschichte," however, which usually has no
substantially different meaning, is interpreted by Heidegger in
the literal sense derived from the German word geschehen, i.e., to
occur or to happen. Hence it is used to express the actual
happening of historical events, or history in the making. It is
tempting to coin for this second "historicity" an
artificial term like "occurrency" or
"proceedingness."
However, the
important thing is to understand the phenomenon so designated as
Heidegger interprets it. The historicity of human being consists
primarily in the individual's fate (Schicksal) based on his own
resolvedness (Entschlossenheit) within an inherited yet chosen
frame of possibilities. There is both impotence and freedom in
such an existence. The foundation of historicity is the
temporality of human being as outlined above. As was the case with
temporality, the center of gravity of historicity lies in the
future. For human being is oriented toward the future, ultimately
toward man's only authentic possibility, death. From this final
"shipwreck" it is thrown back to its facticity, which
gives it pastness (Gewesenheit). In taking over the inherited
possibility of its 'thrownness' (Geworfenheit) it can become
instantaneous (augenblicklich) in its time (p. 385). Resolvedness
allows us to recapture the past in the form of a tradition, which
is in a literal sense a re-petition or re-acquisition
(Wieder-holung).
In mentioning these
aspects one has to admit that an attempt to convey a concise
picture of Heidegger's hermeneutics of historicity is particularly
risky, not only because of its unusually top-heavy formulation,
but also because of its position at the end of the published part
of Sein und Zeit, thus presupposing the assimilation of the
essentials of the preceding interpretations. Hence it would make
little sense to attempt an evaluation, however tentative, of the
phenomenological merits of these analyses. Even without that, it
is possible to acknowledge the originality of Heidegger's attack
upon the problem of history's place in human existence. It keeps
away equally from a blind worship of history as an enslavement to
the past, and from a futile rebellion against it. Even though it
leaves too many obscurities and
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
339
ambiguities, it
points the way toward intensified phenomenological studies of the
historical consciousness and history's place in human existence.
C. PHENOMENOLOGY IN
HEIDEGGER'S PHILOSOPHY
since 'Sein und
Zeit' - The fact that the term "phenomenology" has
practically disappeared from Heidegger's writings since Sein und
Zeit has been mentioned above. It is perhaps even more significant
that even his own expression 'hermeneutics' no longer occurs. Does
this mean that the phenomenological method and its hermeneutic
modification have disappeared along with these terms? That this is
not entirely the case may be gathered from the passage in the
"Brief uber den Humanismus" quoted on p. 279, which
reaffirmed the "essential aid" of phenomenological
seeing while rejecting the "improper aspiration to science
and research." The real question is therefore to what extent
and in what sense phenomenology can still be said to be a decisive
factor in the structure of Heidegger's thought. The answer to this
question depends chiefly on an adequate understanding of
Heidegger's new approach to Being, for which he uses the plain
German word Denken. Besides, we shall have to consider Heidegger's
new attitude toward method in general, as expressed in his ideas
about "ways of thinking" (Denkwege).
What does Heidegger
in his later writings mean by "thinking" ? Certainly
nothing like the techniques of abstract reasoning as studied by
logic in the technical sense, which Heidegger repudiates as a form
of mere technology. Even more important is the fact that he does
not conceive of thinking in the way Kant and Husserl did, namely
as the opposite of Anschauung or intuiting and as restricted to
concepts. The main task in clarifying the phenomenological status
of Heidegger's Denken is to determine the place of what, in the
phenomenological tradition, had been called intuiting (Anschauung)
in the structure of Denken.
Denken, after
having been introduced as the main correlate to Being and Truth in
a rather casual fashion, finally became the subject of Heidegger's
lecture course of 1951 and 52, published in 1954. Here the way in
which Heidegger tried to elucidate the structure of thinking is
based partly on etymology, partly on the translation of a fragment
from Parmenides.
340 THE GERMAN
PHASE
The etymological
approach leads to the interpretation of thinking as Gedanc (a
medieval German word), Andacht (i.e., literally, worshipful
meditation), and Dank (i.e., thanksgiving). By Gedanc Heidegger
understands the "collected, all-collecting remembrance"
also identified with Gemut or heart, very much after the model of
Pascal's logique du coew. Actually Heidegger regards
logico-rational thought as a narrowed-down version of Gedanc,
which includes remembrance (Gedachtnis) in the sense of holding
fast to what is collected. It also implies affection ( Zuneigung)
of the heart toward what is made present by thinking in the sense
of a thanks-giving of listening reverence toward the things to
which we are indebted. All these hints, based on intensified
interpretations of root meanings, add up to a conception of
thinking as an intent and reverent meditation with our whole being
on what makes the content of our thinking. "Being
mindful" might be the nearest English equivalent of such a
conception.
The approach via
the Parmenides text uses a passage usually translated as "It
is necessary to say and to think that Being is" (fragment 6).
Without following Heidegger's highly characteristic discussion all
the way, I shall concentrate on his interpretations of the terms
'saying' (Greek: legein) and 'thinking' (Greek: noein). Legein is
understood primarily as making something lie (or appear) before us
(vorliegen lassen); noein is taken to mean not merely a receptive
process but an active taking before us: we take something into our
heed or guard (in die Acht), leaving it, however, exactly as it is
(D 123 f.). The two are inseparable parts of thinking. Taking
something into our heed is described as making what lies before us
come toward us. It is not a reaching out (Zugreifen) toward it (D
127) nor any attack upon it. More important, it is not a matter of
concept (Begriff). Thus while "thinking" thinks in
accordance with the things, it thinks without concepts; according
to Heidegger this is true even of thinking in the sense of
Aristotle.
What can be derived
from these characterizations, which never add up to a sustained
description of what goes on concretely in a specific case of
thinking ? Clearly, this thinking is anything but a methodical
procedure for which definite rules could be prescribed. It is a
matter of the whole human thinker, including
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
341
his heart as well
as his intellect, insofar as this distinction is still
permissible. It seems to be neither completely receptive nor
spontaneous, but in any case it stands under the commanding
guidance of the object of thought, i.e., Being, which determines
its content.
Is it possible to
identify such a non-conceptual thinking simply with intuition in
the old phenomenological sense? No explicit statement for or
against such an interpretation can be found in Heidegger's own
writings. In answer to a personal inquiry Heidegger intimated that
he avoids the terms "Anschauung" and
"Intuition" chiefly because of their past associations,
among them, it may be assumed, with Husserl's Wesensschau. It
should also be noted that the operations of thinking as
characterized above are hardly those in which we are actually
cognizant. At best these operations precede or follow cognition.
The etymological interpretation of thinking in the sense of
"being mindful" and the one based on the Parmenides
text, according to which thinking makes its object lie before us,
seems to refer to a phase which prepares actual cognition, while
"taking under one's guard" describes one that follows
it. However, even though Heidegger's account of thinking does not
mention the cognitive phase explicitly, he certainly does not
exclude it. But is this sufficient ground for asserting that
thinking is identical with the phenomenological intuition ?
Heidegger's later
writings contain little reference to method in the traditional
sense. But there is all the more frequent reference to a motif
which is actually a translation of the Greek word methodos (i.e.,
"way after") namely, "way of thinking"
(Denk-weg). These Denkwege occur particularly in two types. One of
them carries the German title Holzwege, i.e., forest paths or
roads that chiefly serve the lumbermen but to everyone else are
nothing but blind alleys; whence 'auf dem Holzweg sein' means
colloquially 'to be on the wrong track.' Heidegger uses this word
as the title for six long essays seemingly without mutual
connection. Only in his mystagogic prologue does he hint that the
lumbermen and the rangers )(Waldhuter, reminding us of the
"guardians of Being") "know" these paths. The
Feldweg, however, designating a private winding country path
through the fields, is used by Heidegger as the title of a
charming autobio-
342 THE GERMAN
PHASE
graphical
reminiscence.1 This path seems to assume almost the role of a
messenger of truth and even of a comforter to man. Thus, in the
unarticulated language of the things around the Feldweg, "God
is finally God." Yet the last message of the Feldweg remains
in a resigned chiaroscuro: "The message (Zu-spruch) is now
quite distinct. Is it the soul that speaks? Is it the world ? Is
it God ? Everything speaks of resignation to the same thing. ...
It grants the inexhaustible power of the simple" (das
Einfache).
None of Heidegger's
later "ways" has the nature of an easy royal road or
even of a normal highway. They are all byways. There is no
assurance as to their destination nor any claim to universal
validity. And there is no clear prescription telling us how to use
them. Thinking consists in a being "underway," which
actually builds the way.2 It is also a lonely way. And Heidegger
even seems to doubt the advisability of making this way
"publicly visible." Thus "thinking," even
insofar as it is in our power and not simply a response to the
initiative of Being, is clearly nothing that can be put into the
form of a method to be taught and learned.
There are other
characteristic proofs for this conclusion. In his decisive attempt
to force the proper translation and interpretation of the
Parmenides text quoted above Heidegger speaks about the necessity
of a leap, the leap of a single glance (Blick) which catches sight
of what Parmenides meant. This almost sounds like Kierkegaard's
celebrated leap into faith. Apparently we can prepare for such a
leap. But Heidegger does not tell us how (p. 141). One can only
tell what he sees in such a leap. But reasons and counter-reasons
are ineffective. More recently Heidegger, playing on the double
meaning of the word "Satz" in German as
"proposition" and as "leap," even used such
fundamental logical propositions as the "law of sufficient
reason" and the "law of identity" as starting
points for a leap into Being whose abruptness does not allow for
any methodical approach.3
Another indication
of the non-methodical character of the new "thought" is
Heidegger's repudiation of the term "research."
1 See also Hohwege,
p, 194;. Vortrdge und Aufsatze, p. 184.
2 Was heisst
Denken?, p. 164.
3 Der Satz vom
Grund, p. 95 f., 157; Identitdt und Differenz, p. 24 f.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
343
To him research is
the mark of modern science, which is characterized by a certain
preconception (Entwurf) of its field and by its method. The
researcher becomes actually a technician in the service of the
conquest of the world by the subject man. Reflection (Besinnung),
which Heidegger contrasts to this research as the proper task of
philosophy, apparently cannot be described in terms of a clear and
teachable method.1 Even more indicative of this non-methodical
character of the new kind of thinking is its affinity with poetry,
as Heidegger conceives of it and even practices it. It would
exceed the possibilities and needs of this discussion to give an
account and attempt a clarification of what Heidegger means by
poetry. But it is clear that it goes far beyond the creation of a
merely imaginative world. Poetry not only finds truth, it even
establishes it, says Heidegger, using one of his favorite but
enigmatic words "stiffen." It "names" the
Holy, and is thus the road toward the Divine and indirectly toward
God.2 In any case, poetry is a parallel enterprise to thinking, in
its highest achievements even superior to thinking. At times
Heidegger now seems to think of thinking itself as merely a form
of poetry.3 Certainly there are no longer any sharp borderlines
between them. And both seem to be much more under the guidance and
control of Being than of man, the poet or thinker.
This poses the
question of whether there are any tests for this kind of thinking.
Heidegger himself raises it in connection with one of his boldest,
most forced interpretative translations. Here he admits that no
scientific proof is possible, but he also rejects mere faith.
Instead, "Thinking is the poetry (Dichten) of truth of Being
in the historical dialogue of the thinkers" (geschichttiche
Zwiesprache der Denker).* This dialogue is a recurrent motif in
Heidegger's philosophizing. But it is obviously not so much
dialogues among contemporaries which he has in mind. Some of
these, like the meeting between Heidegger and Ernst Cassirer in
1929 were memorable events.5 But they have hardly modified or
tested anyone's beliefs, but were chiefly public confrontations.
1 Holzwege, p. 69;
translated by Marjorie Grene in Measure II, 269 ff. See also
Vortrdge und Aufsatze, p. 45 ff.
2 Was ist
Metaphysik? Nachwort (1934), 6th edition, p. 46.
3 Aus der Erfahrung
des Denkens, p. 25; Holzwege, p. 343. < Holzwege, p. 302 f.,
343.
5 See, e.g. Hendrik
J. Pos, "Recollections of Ernst Cassirer" in Schilpp.
P., ed., The Philosophy of Ernst Cassirer, pp. 67-69; Sein und
Zeit, p. 51 f.
344 THE GERMAN
PHASE
The dialogue which
is the testing ground for Heidegger is that with the texts of the
great thinkers of the past, to whose interpretation he seems to
have turned as his favorite approach to the problems. However, a
dialogue in which the real partner is silenced from the very start
offers little guarantee that we shall hear anything but an echo of
the speaker's own voice. In fact, Heidegger himself seems to be
aware that his own interpretations are by no means valid for all
times nor, for that matter, for anyone else but himself.1
What has become at
this stage of Heidegger's earlier interpretation of phenomenology,
notably of his hermeneutics ? We remember that the ground for such
a phenomenology was laid by the so-called phenomenological
destruction. Even without using the name, Heidegger has continued
this technique, especially in his Holzwege, where, for instance,
the discussions of Nietzsche and Anaximander offer excellent
examples of it. Here a searching interpretation of the texts
serves as preparation for a more original approach to the
phenomena.
It is less easy to
say what has become of the hermeneutic method of Sein und Zeit.
For it is not only the term that has disappeared: human being, the
one and only subject of such interpretation, no longer constitutes
the privileged topic of Heidegger's investigations. The themes of
his later thinking are no longer taken from such a limited area,
but include not only works of art but also aspects of Being
itself. This means that interpretation no longer takes the
exclusive form of uncovering the true purposes of human being. But
this does not mean that interpretation as such is abandoned. To be
sure, it is not Being itself or truth which requires Auslegung.
Now it is primarily texts which form the starting points for
Heidegger's own philosophizing. Their interpretation had been a
constant concern of Heidegger's lectures and seminars, beginning
with his Aristotle interpretations of 1921/22. The first
large-scale example to reach the wider public was the Kant book.
The explanation of Holderlin's poetry, beginning in 1936, applied
this interpretation to a new area. Holzwege, especially in the
case of the fragment from Anaximander, gave a first sample of
Heidegger's interpretation of Pre-Socratic texts, which were
followed by the Parmenides
1 Was heisst
Denken? p. 110.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
345
interpretations in
Was heisst Denken ? But how do these interpretations differ from
the scholarly interpretations of the philologists ? True,
Heidegger often begins with a careful study of the texts. But he
wants his analysis to be clearly distinguished from merely
philological interpretation, for which he shows little taste or
respect. For he is not afraid of doing violence to his texts in
order to "understand" a thinker better than he has
understood himself, whether his name is Kant or Plato. "In
contrast to the methods of historical philology, which has its own
task, a thinking dialogue is subject to different laws." !
Whatever the
methods and limitations of these new interpretations of given
texts may be, in what sense can they be claimed to be
phenomenology, even if they should still be hermeneutics ? The
answer must depend on the extent to which they still deal with
phenomena, even if this term is understood in Heidegger's own
sense of "what shows itself by itself." It could hardly
be claimed that texts as such, poetic or otherwise, are such
phenomena. Hence it would be rather inappropriate to describe
their interpretation as genuinely phenomenological.
How far, in fact,
do Heidegger's last writings deal directly with phenomena? The
"unhiddenness" of Truth and Being would seem to make
hermeneutic interpretation superfluous. On the other hand
"truth," being merely the "clearing" within
Being, leaves enough darkness around it to challenge the
hermeneutic thinker. However, as long as Heidegger himself does
not offer such a hermeneutics of Being and of Truth, and
especially as long as he does not do so explicitly and in some
detail, it would be premature to label his present preludes to it
as a hermeneutics of Being.
It should also be
noticed that Heidegger's thinking has now abandoned all pretense
of being "scientific." The hermeneutic phenomenology of
Sein und Zeit, even in its "definitive concept," still
tried to be science and seemed to maintain Husserl's original
aspirations toward a rigorous science. How far this amounts to a
difference in Heidegger's actual procedure rather than to a
difference in his self-interpretation is another matter. But it
highlights again the degree to which Heidegger has drifted
1 Kant und das
Problem der Metaphysik. Preface to the 2nd ed., 1950.
346 THE GERMAN
PHASE
away from his
original conception of phenomenology and his hopes for it.
In conclusion, I
should mention the fact that in September 1953 I had a unique
opportunity to interview Martin Heidegger personally about his
present attitude toward phenomenology. Without quoting his words,
I feel entitled to render the sense of his answers as follows:
Heidegger frankly admitted and restated his rejection of
transcendental phenomenology. But he did not express any intention
of dissociating himself from the Phenomenological Movement, as far
as its general substance is concerned. Nor did he say or imply
that any substantial change in his methods had taken place since
the publication of Sein und Zeit, particularly not with regard to
such innovations as the phenomenological destruction and
phenomenological hermeneutics. As far as the abandonment of Sein
und Zeit is concerned, he intimated that the new approach from
Being to human being by no means excluded the earlier one from
human being to Being. In fact he stated that if he ever should
rewrite Sein und Zeit he would try to combine the two approaches.
In other words, for Heidegger this is a matter of a both-and, not
of an either-or.
I shall not attempt
to discuss this self-interpretation in the light of the evidence
already presented. In any event, Heidegger did not deny the
obvious shift in his approach. He thus confirmed my conjecture
that phenomenology, understood as the hermeneutic interpretation
of human being, has lost its priority in the pattern of his
thinking. How far there can be any such thing as a phenomenology
within the framework of the later approach must remain an open
question. Heidegger does refer to the "essential aid of
phenomenological seeing." However, there are no conspicuous
examples of it in his later writings except those strewn in among
his interpretations of texts. This is one reason why no
illustrations of this later phenomenological thinking will be
added here. Heidegger's original phenomenology remains that of
Sein und Zeit.
6. Toward an
Appraisal of Heidegger's Phenomenology
I began the attempt
to introduce Heidegger's phenomenology by a remarkable tribute
taken from Gilbert Ryle's review of Sein und Zeit. It would,
however, be misleading to conceal the
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
347
fact that in spite
of his sympathetic approach to Heidegger's text he came out with a
rather disastrous estimate of his phenomenology. His final
conclusion concerning its significance for the entire
Phenomenological Movement seems worth pondering even in
retrospect:
It is my personal
opinion that qua First Philosophy Phenomenology is at present
heading for bankruptcy and disaster and will end either in
self-ruinous Subjectivism or in a windy Mysticism. ... I hazard
this opinion with humility and reservations, since I am well aware
how far I have fallen short of understanding this difficult work.
At least to some
extent this modest prophecy, read with all its qualifications, has
come true. It has proved so at least for that part of the German
phenomenology of the thirties with which Ryle was acquainted (he
clearly was not with Scheler). For Husserl's radicalized
subjectivism failed to produce the promised final systematic
statement in a version that satisfied the master himself
sufficiently to authorize publication.
As to Heidegger's
phenomenology, Ryle anticipated remarkably the trend toward an
increasingly mystic approach. And since Heidegger had captured the
minds of most German phenomenologists and "stolen the
show," as it were, his final abandonment of the label
"phenomenology" can be interpreted as the liquidation if
not as the bankruptcy of the Movement. The fact that even
Husserl's erstwhile assistants, Ludwig Land-grebe and Eugen Fink,
have declared phenomenology a closed chapter could be considered
as the final confirmation of the prophecy.
But whether or not
it has proved correct, more important than the prognosis is the
diagnosis, which in Ryle's case is more than debatable. The
following attempt to evaluate Heidegger's phenomenology is not
meant as an assessment of his philosophizing as a whole. Its
limited objective will be (1) to determine to what extent
Heidegger's philosophy was really phenomenology and hence can be
taken as representative of phenomenology as such:
(2) to point out
the peculiar strengths and weaknesses of Heidegger's
phenomenologizing.
a. TO WHAT EXTENT
IS HEIDEGGER A PHENOMENOLOGIST? Clearly Heidegger never was a
phenomenologist
348 THE GERMAN
PHASE
in the strictest
sense defined by Husserl's subjectivist transcendentalism with its
idealistic implications, even though, especially at the time of
Sein und Zeit, he rejected traditional realism. In particular, he
never accepted the phenomenological reduction in Husserl's sense.
As to the strict
sense of phenomenology, in which attention to the ways of
givenness becomes essential (sense y). the hermeneutic analyses of
Sein und Zeit hold at least considerable implicit interest. This
is particularly evident in the interpretation of moods as
revealing more or less indirectly the fundamental situation of
human being.
It may be more
dubious whether Heidegger's phenomenology fits into the framework
of a phenomenology in the wider sense, which emphasizes the
insights into essences (sense p). For hermeneutic phenomenology
intends to treat human existence as each one's own, although one
might say that in the final analysis it still gives a diagnosis of
human existence in general. It should also be mentioned that quite
often Heidegger speaks of certain features as
"essentially" belonging to Being or thinking, and even
refers to essential laws, which would seem to imply that he at
least practices eidetic phenomenology even if he does not want to
preach it.
It is, however, by
no means clear whether Heidegger belongs any longer
unconditionally within the framework of the Phenomenological
Movement in the widest sense oc. The first test, acceptance of
intuiting as the ultimate source and test of all knowledge, could
be justified probably even in the case of Heidegger's later
philosophy of thinking, in which phenomenological seeing is
appealed to as an essential help, if not as the substance of his
approach. What is more questionable is whether he still identifies
himself actively with the Phenomenological Movement, even if he
does not dissociate himself from it completely. Perhaps the real
question is whether Heidegger still recognized the survival of
such a Movement at all. Certainly he himself does not give
evidence of any active interest in its continuation or revival.
Summing up, we must
remember: Phenomenology was for Heidegger fundamentally only a
means for the solution of his basic problem. This means proved to
be only partially effective. It never was an integral part of his
philosophy. Heidegger had
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
349
come to Husserl's
phenomenology with his task all laid out. In the days of his
emancipation from scholastic and transcen-dentalist philosophy
(Rickert), and especially after meeting Husserl, he thought that a
hermeneutic phenomenology of human being (in contrast to Husserl's
descriptive phenomenology of pure consciousness) offered the best
chance for the solution of his problem. His failure to win over
Husserl to this approach and the ensuing rift between them were
factors in his retreat from phenomenology in the technical sense.
More important was the realization that the approach to the
problem of Being via an analysis of human being was not the hoped
for master key to the riddle of Being, since the transition from
the temporality of human being to the time of Being itself could
not be made. It was this retreat from the prerogative of the
subjective in the sense of the human which entailed his detachment
from phenomenology with its primary interest in the given as
given. Phenomenology, insofar as it is still a part of Heidegger's
recent approach, is no longer its decisive part. It was
fundamentally nothing but a phase in his development. No wonder he
now seems disinterested in its present and future.
This conclusion
does not discharge us from an evaluation of Heidegger's concrete
phenomenological achievements. In what follows I shall therefore
offer some observations on the points that seem to me relevant to
such a more detailed appraisal beyond the incidental remarks that
have been made in earlier sections of this chapter.
b. STRENGHTS AND
WEAKNESSES OF HEIDEGGER'S PHENOMENOLOGY - There can be little
question that in his hermeneutic phenomenology Heidegger has
attacked a variety of phenomena, such as fear, anxiety, and
concern, which had not been taken up before by phenomenologists,
and that he has brought out some of their aspects and characters
in a way that shows his unusual perceptiveness and penetration.
Nevertheless,
Heidegger's accounts of these phenomena, taken as phenomenological
descriptions, are often meager, chiefly because he usually limits
himself to attaching to these phenomena striking and evocative
names instead of determining their constituent elements, their
varieties, and their comparative
350 THE GERMAN
PHASE
characteristics.
This lack is clearly related to the fact that Heidegger considers
the task of a mere description of manifest phenomena to be
superfluous. The concern of his hermeneutic phenomenology is to
uncover the hidden phenomena and particularly their meanings.
However, the question seems legitimate whether in this regard
Heidegger does not share the naivete of many explanatory sciences
which overlook the fact that what is manifest is not always
thoroughly perceived, assimilated, and understood in its structure
and its varieties. It is for such reasons that the descriptive
basis for Heidegger's interpretations is often too narrow.
This raises the
whole question of the rights of hermeneutic phenomenology.
Difficult though it may be, Heidegger's program of a phenomenology
that attempts to investigate the hidden aspects of the phenomena
(the "phenomenological" phenomena) is more than
justifiable, particularly if it can succeed in making them
directly accessible rather than leaving them in the realm of
merely hypothetical explanations which can be only indirectly
verified. This applies particularly to the hermeneutic
interpretations of human being and existence. Doubts concerning
them apply more to the practice than to the principle of this
obviously ambitious and difficult enterprise. Rarely if ever does
Heidegger seem to consider the possibility of interpretations
other than his own. And often, for instance in his discussion of
moods, one cannot overcome the impression of a biased approach
which prevents him from considering alternatives. Never does he
seem to feel the need of showing his readers his criteria. There
is a finality about his monumental and oracular pronouncements
which ignores the question of evidence and strains the critical
sense of all but the devotees.
If one recalls the
caution and carefulness which characterized the work of the early
phenomenologists, one cannot help being amazed at the blitheness
with which the new phenomenology takes, for instance, the
manifestness (Offenbarkeit) of Being for granted. The seeming
qualification that Being also tends to hide, or that we are
forgetful of it, does but little to relieve the stunning boldness
of the claim. If we are also told that it is Being itself which
plays this game of hide and seek on a cosmic scale, it seems hard
to avoid the impression of a fantastic drama with-
351
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
out personal
protagonists. Surely, in the name of a critical phenomenology such
claims must not go unchallenged.
Lack of patience
with the critical reader leads to what is perhaps the severest
handicap of Heidegger's phenomenology:
the difficulty of
its formulation and transmission. In raising this point one must
not minimize the creative originality and power of Heidegger's
diction and style. If these qualities alone could determine the
rank of philosophy, there would be no question in my mind that
Heidegger's achievement is unique. There is a certain grandeur in
his writing, even if in places but one step separates the sublime
from the ridiculous.
But there are
requirements for philosophical language other than style.
Heidegger himself, who has thought deeply about language, has an
extremely high conception of its nature and capacities. Perhaps
its most exalted formulation is implied in the statement:
"Language is the house of being. In this house man has his
abode." 1 It is for this reason, too, that ultimately poetry,
in preference to the non-verbal arts, receives such a preferred
rank in Heidegger's thinking.
In view of this
estimate it is all the more significant that precisely
difficulties of language, the "house of being," have
blocked the way of Sein und Zeit beyond its published parts and
have apparently interfered even with the development of
Heidegger's second approach in Vom Wesen der Wahrheit (see p.
311). To be sure, it is the language of metaphysics which failed,
not language as such. But what language can supplant it ? Hardly
the language of the poet, who "names the Holy," but does
not "tell Being," as the "thinker" is expected
to do.
This difficulty
leads to the even more serious, and in a sense gravest, crux of
Heidegger's phenomenology: its communicability through language.
Heidegger's obvious intent to awaken and even to shock his reader
into a realization of the phenomena has all too often defeated his
own purpose. The squeezing and bending of existing words by
literalizing their meanings, whether etymologically justified or
not, without additional guidance to the reader by way of
definitions or examples, is apt to create a twilight of uncritical
semi-understanding among the gullible, and of hostile
misunderstanding among the more critical. True,
1 "Brief fiber
den Humanismus" in Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit, p. 53.
352 THE GERMAN
PHASE
phenomenology has
always had to face the problem of devising new terms for new
phenomena. But it has never been enough to coin such terms without
also introducing the reader to the new phenomena. Just this is one
of the functions of a descriptive phenomenology. Lack of patience
and empathy with his readers is the worst weakness of Heidegger's
hermeneutic phenomenology. It reduces it to a more or less private
enterprise or esoteric cult. Yet it would seem to me that this is
by no means an irremediable weakness, and that it should be
possible to salvage a good deal of Heidegger's insights by a less
reckless and violent approach to the problem of communication. It
may well be that the success of French phenomenology, including
its Heideggerian ingredients, is due to greater concern for this
problem.
One final doubt is
raised by the approach of Heidegger's later writings.
Phenomenology in its early stage was characterized by its
courageous attack on the things themselves, regardless of previous
opinions and theories. There is in Heidegger an increasing
tendency to go to the "things" by way of classical texts
and by an interpretation based primarily on etymology and at best
secondarily on an appeal to the phenomena. It is thus again the
secondary world of books and traditions which gets between the
"things" and their fresh intuition. To be sure, it would
be a sad loss if phenomenology should deprive itself completely of
the insights of the past, which now also include the insights of
the earlier phenomenologists. But it would be just as fatal if
"going to the sources" should again assume the sense of
going to the texts, instead of going to the phenomena. The way
from Sein und Zeit to Was heisst Denken? shows an alarming
tendency in this direction.
Once in the
twenties, in one of his exuberant moods at the height of his
cooperation with Heidegger, Husserl exclaimed:
"Phenomenology,
that is Heidegger and me." Had it been so, Ryle's prophecy
would indeed have come true. But here, as in Husserl's case, I
shall invoke Heidegger's own words, with which he vindicated his
independence of Husserl in Sein und Zeit: "The essence of
phenomenology does not consist in its actuality. Higher than
actuality stands potentiality."
Later chapters will
tell the story of the development of these unexhausted
potentialities.
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
353
7. Heidegger's
Following and Phenomenology
Compared with the
academic influence of other phenomenologists such as Husserl and
Scheler, Heidegger has unquestionably the largest following. Even
some of Husserl's Freiburg students like landgrebe and fink have
come so much under the influence of Heidegger that a recent
bibliography of German philosophy of existence may be justified in
including them among his "immediate students." 1 Others
include oskar becker, F. J. brecht, walter brocker, hans Georg
Gadamer, Gerhard Kruger, Karl Lowith (the last two among his
keenest critics), wilhelm szilasi, his Freiburg successor, and
karl-heinz volkmann-schluck. Beyond them there is a widening
circle of thinkers inside and outside Germany who are more or less
his disciples in the non-academic sense.2
It is another
question whether these followers practice Heidegger's
phenomenology. No sweeping answer to such a question should be
given without detailed conscientious examination. However, on the
whole, there is in the literature of the Heideggerians little
explicit reference to phenomenology. Some of Oskar Becker's
studies, particularly his earlier ones, those of Karl Lowith, and
in a wider sense perhaps even those of 0. F. Bollnow would seem to
be most phenomenological in character. So is the work of the Swiss
psychiatrist Ludwig Binswanger, which owes much to both Husseri
and Heidegger, though he finally emancipated himself even from
Heidegger.
Then there is the
question of the extent to which Heidegger's followers have
maintained the level set by the master. It is one thing to
practice a thinking as unique and self-willed as Heidegger's. It
is another matter to duplicate it without imitating the mannerisms
of the master and especially the artificialities of his language.
Unfortunately, the result has been too often turgid imitation,
combined with an uncritical worship of the words of the master.
1 O. F. Bollnow,
Deutsche Existenzphilosophie (Bern, Francke, 1953).
2 Werner Brock, the
editor of Existence and Being, is one of these. - See also the
list of contributors to the two Festschrift volumes published, on
the occasion of Heidegger's 60th birthday.
354 THE GERMAN
PHASE
SELECTIVE
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Major Works
Die Kategorien- und
Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus (1916) Sein und Zeit. I. Halfte
(1927) (SZ)
Translations:
Spanish (1951) by Jose Gaos; French (excerpts from the second
section in Qu'est-ce que la metaphysique? (1938) by H. Corbin;
an English
translation is promised by Blackwell's. "Vom Wesen des
Grundes" in Festschrift fur E. Husserl (1929)
Translations:
French (1930 and 1938) by H. Corbin Kant und das Problem der
Metaphysik (1929)
Translations:
French (1954) by W. Biemel and A. de Waelhens Was ist Metaphysik:?
(1929) - Nachwort (1944); Einleitung (1951)
Translations:
French (1931 and 1938); Spanish (1933); English (1949) by R. F. C.
Hull and Alan Crick in Existence and Being, edited by Werner
Brock1 - a careful, conscientious effort. The
"Einleitung," translated by Walter Kaufmann, appeared in
his Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre (1957), pp. 207-21
Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universitat (1933) Holderlin
und das Wesen der Dichtung (1936)
Translations:
French (1938); English (1949) by Douglas Scott in Existence and
Being - fair. Vom Wesen der Wahrheit (1943)
Translations:
French (1949) by A. de Waelhens and W. Biemel;
English (1949) by
R. F. C. Hull and Alan Crick in Existence and Being -good. Platons
Lehre von der Wahrheit (1947)
Contains also the
"Brief uber den Humanismus" an Jean Beaufret. Holzwege
(1950)
Translations:
English (1951), second essay only, by Mar j one Grene in Measure
(1951), 269 ff. Einfuhrung in die Metaphysik (1953)
Translations:
English (1958) by Ralph Manheim - on the whole reliable and
readable, though not as close to the original as possible. Was
heisst Denken? (1954) (D) A us der Erfahrung des Denkens (1954?)
Vortrage und Aufsatze (1954) Was ist das ~ die Philosophic? (1956)
Translations:
English (1958) by W. Kluback and Jean T. Wilde with German text
added. Der Satz vom Grund (1957) Identitat und Differenz (1957)
1 "Existence
and Being," a title not used by Heidegger himself,
characterizes very well the poles of his thinking, but is hardly
indicative of the content of a volume two thirds of which consist
of Brock's helpful paraphrase of Sein und Seit, followed by the
translation of four original essays in the last third. These
essays, selected by Heidegger himself for the occasion and even
prefaced by a brief "Note" (p. 249), are a puzzling
combination, especially if meant as an introduction for
Anglo-American readers, since two of the four essays are
interpretations of Holderlin poems, which are put before the two
metaphysical essays. Heidegger himself seems to be merely
concerned lest they be considered as -'contributions to research
in the history of literature and esthetics," which he
deprecates, pleading merely that the four essays "arose from
a necessity of thought."
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
355
Monographs in
French and German biemel, walter, Le concept de monde chez
Heidegger, Louvain, Nauwe-
laerts, 1950
Careful analysis of
a central concept in Heidegger's thought against the
background of the
problem of Being, based chiefly on his earlier work. furstenau,
peter, Heidegger, Das Gefuge seines Denkens. Frankfurt,
Klostermann, 1958
A well-informed
attempt to show the unity of Heidegger's thought
from Sein und Zeit
to the latest works. gaos, jose, Introduccidn a el Ser y el Tiempo
de Martin Heidegger. Mexico,
1951 lowith, karl,
Heidegger, Denker in durftiger Zeit. Frankfurt, Fischer,
1953
A series of three
penetrating studies on the development of Heidegger's
thought, pointing
out important changes in his later work.
de waelhens,
alphonse, La philosophic de Martin Heidegger. Louvain, Institut
superieur, 1942
Thus far the most
detailed study of Heidegger's central works up to 1942, focussing
on his existential analytics, but including a discussion of its
phenomenological features.
---, Phenomenologie
et verite. Essai sur revolution de I'idee de verite chez Husserl
et Heidegger. Paris, Presses Universitaires, 1953 The second and
larger part of this perceptive study deals with the fate of the
idea of truth in Heidegger's thought, including his later works.
Large Studies in
English:1
grene, marjorie,
Martin Heidegger. New York, Hilary, 1957
An informed but not
altogether sympathetic brief interpretation, omitting a number of
central doctrines. The connections with phenomenology are hardly
mentioned. Important passages are given in both German and
English.
langan, thomas, The
Meaning of Heidegger. A Critical Study of an Existentialist
Phenomenology. New York, Columbia, 1959 An attempt to show the
unity of Heidegger's work. Its phenomenological aspect is only
named but never explained
Articles in English
cerf, walter,
"An Approach to Heidegger's Ontology," PPR I (1940),
177-90
delius, harald,
"Descriptive Interpretation," PPR XIII (1953), 305-23
earle, william, "Wahl on Heidegger on Being,"
Philosophical Review
LXVII (1958), 85-90
1 The
Anglo-American reader will find considerable help in the Heidegger
chapters of several books on existentialism, especially in Alien,
E. L., Existentialism from Within; Blackham, H. J., Six
Existentialist Thinkers (1951), Ch. V.; Collins, James, The
Existentialists (1952), Ch. V.; Kuhn, Helmut, Encounter with
Nothingness (1951) (where especially the connections between
phenomenology and existentialism in Heidegger are discussed very
helpfully in Ch. VIII). But few of these much too comprehensive
accounts are free from factual errors.
356 THE GERMAN
PHASE
farber, marvin,
"Heidegger on the Essence of Truth," PPR XVIII (1958),
523-32
freund, E. H.,
"Man's Fall in Heidegger's Philosophy," Journal of
Religion XXIV (1944), 180-87
glicksman (grene),
marjorie, "A Note on the Philosophy of Heidegger,"
Jownalof Philosophy XXXV (1938), 93-104 (Student impressions from
Freiburg 1931-2).
gray, J. glenn,
"Heidegger's "Being," Journal of Philosophy, XLIX
(1952), 415-22.
(Clear account of Heidegger's later philosophy)
---,
"Heidegger's Course: From Human Existence to Nature,"
Journal of Philosophy LIV (1957), 197-207
---,
"Heidegger Evaluates Nietzsche," J. of History of Ideas
XIV
(1953), 304-9.
hinners, richard,
"The Freedom and Finiteness of Existence in Heidegger,"
New Scholasticism XXXIII (1959), 32-48
kaufmann, F. W.,
"The Value of Heidegger's Analysis of Existence for Literary
Criticism," Modern Language Notes XLVIII (1933), 487-91
kraft, julius,
"The Philosophy of Existence," PPR I (1941), 339-58
Discussion by Fritz Kaufmann I, 359-64 and rejoinder 364-5.
lowith, karl,
"Heidegger: Problem and Background of Existentialism,"
Social Research XV (1948), 345-69
---, "M.
Heidegger and F. Rosenzweig on Temporality and Eternity,"
PPR III (1943),
53-77 marx, werner, "Heidegger's New Concept of Philosophy.
The Second
Phase of
Existentialism," Social Research XXII (1953), 451-74 merlan,
philip, "Time Consciousness in Husserl and Heidegger,"
PPR
VIII (1948), 23-53
richey, clarence W., "On the Intentional Ambiguity of
Heidegger's
Metaphysics,"
Journal of Philosophy LVIII (1958), 1144-48 schrader, george,
"Heidegger's Ontology of Human Existence,"
Review of
Metaphysics X (1956), 35-56 schrag, calvin, 0.,
"Phenomenology, Ontology, and History in the
Philosophy of
Heidegger," Revue Internationale de philosophic XII
(1958), 117-32
stern, guenther
(anders), "On the Pseudo-Concreteness of Heidegger's
Philosophy," PPR VIII (1948), 337-71
strasser, stephen,
"The Concept of Dread in the Philosophy of Heidegger,"
Modern Schoolman XXXV (1957), 1-20 taubes, S. A., "The
Gnostic Foundations of Heidegger's Nihilism,"
Journal of Religion
XXXIV (1954), 155-72 tint, H., "Heidegger and the
Irrational," Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society LVII
(1957), 253-68 trivers, howard, "Heidegger's
Misinterpretation of Hegel's Views on
Spirit and
Time," PPR III (1943), 162-68 turnbull, robert G.,
"Heidegger on the Nature of Truth," Journal of
Philosophy LVII
(1957), 559-65 weiss, helene, "The Greek Conception of Time
and Being in the Light
of Heidegger's
Philosophy," PPR II (1942), 173-87 werkmeister, W. H.,
"An Introduction to Heidegger's 'Existential
Philosophy',"
PPR II (1941), 79-87
MARTIN HEIDEGGER
357
Ph. D. Theses
glicksman (later
grene), marjorie, The Concept of Existence in Contemporary German
Philosophy. Radcliffe, 1935 hinners, richard C., Heidegger's
Conception of the Question "What is
the Meaning of
to-be?" in Sein und Zeit. Yale, 1955 malik, charles M., The
Metaphysics of Time in the Philosophies of
A. N. Whitehead and
M. Heidegger. Harvard, 1937 stavrides, ria, The Concept of
Existence in Kierkegaard and Heidegger.
Columbia
University, 1952 tweedie, donald F. Jr., The Significance of Dread
in the Thought of
Kierkegaard and
Heidegger. Boston University, 1954 versenyi, laszlo, Heidegger's
Theory of Truth. Yale, 1955 wyschogrod, michael, Kierkegaard and
Heidegger. The Ontology of Existence. Columbia University, 1954;
London, Kegan Paul, 1954
Most Comprehensive
Recent Bibliography
lubbe, hermann,
"Bibliographic der Heidegger Literatur 1917-1955,"
Zeitschrift fur philosophische Forschung XI (1957), 401-52
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Здесь
представлена глава из первого тома
капитального
труда
Шпигельберга посвященная
Хайдеггеру.
******
vispir^press
2001
vispir.narod.ru
|